Post-Autistic Economics Network
More Student
Essays
Home Page
PAE
Review
|
www.paecon.net
Student Essays on Post-Autistic Economics
posted April 2003
Communities
and Social Goods:
The case
of the missing social realm
Rick
Wicks (Doctoral
Candidate, Economics Department, Göteborg
University, Sweden)
The core of economics, insofar as it relates to policy, is directed to keeping
markets running satisfactorily, keeping production efficient and growing,
etc. Related to this market core are three potential problem areas: 1) market
forces may result in poverty, or in income differentials which undermine
democracy and the political environment; 2) market forces may threaten the
natural environment; 3) market forces may threaten the social environment.
Without wishing to slight the market core or either of the other two related
potential problem areas, my concern here is with the latter, the social environment. And while there
is some conceptual overlap (just as there can be with intermediate goods used
in production, which might also be used directly as consumer goods), my
concern is not with social capital
used in production or exchange processes, but with social goods which enter the consumer's
utility function directly.
Many technical problems have been pointed out with neoclassical economic
theory, (e.g., see Keen 2001). But one of the biggest problems with its content -- pace Becker (1976) and others (e.g., Coleman 1990-94, Iannaccone 1998, Becker and Murphy 2000) -- is its
near-total omission of the social realm:
communities and the social goods we derive from them.
Communities are groups based on kinship, location,
or ideology (see Nisbet 1953/70, Bell 1993, and Etzioni & Etzioni 1999),
while social goods are such things
as a sense of purpose, belonging, security, and identity, as well as love and
friendship, even tolerance and common courtesy.
We seem to have a deep need for communities
and social goods (Lewis, Amini, and Lannon 2000), even though it may not always seem
"rational" to invest in them. Many aspects of traditional culture
may have co-evolved in order to guarantee satisfaction of these needs despite
their apparent
"irrationality" (Chwe 2001). Thus it's
not always clear that it's the expected consequences for an individual now which matter; rather, what matters
may well have been what shaped our character primordially, the expected
consequences in the "ancestral environment" in which we evolved
(Wright 1994, Sober and Wilson 1998, Boehm 1999).
Ever since the advent of capitalism, and even
since the much earlier advent of markets (Pryor 1977), many observers have
been concerned about market effects on this social realm of communities and
social goods. Many students are aware of and share these concerns.
But neoclassical economic theory ignores the
social realm almost entirely, not even noting its absence in fundamental
discussions of utility and welfare, which is where "the bullet hits the
bone"; cf. Walras 1874-26/1954, Pigou 1920-32/1962, Arrow 1977/83, Boadway
and Bruce 1984-93, Myles 1995, Jha 1998.
Consequently, policy-advice based on neoclassical
economic theory increases its risk of being highly unrealistic in terms of
true overall social welfare.
And the teaching of neoclassical economics
increases its risk of being sterile and unrewarding, as it is in fact often
found to be.
For economic theory to include (or even to discuss the omission of)
communities and social goods will require recognition that such a social
realm both exists and is different from the market (or economic) realm. As Fullbrook (2001, pp. 7-8) says: "[T]he blockage of
the first phase [of Bhaskar's (1979)
"three-phase schema of scientific development"] -- the identifying
of phenomena -- has stalled economics…" Thus it might be helpful if
economics were to return to one of the most fundamental of scientific
questions, of basic taxonomy (cf. Ruhlen 1994, p.
195): What are the social phenomena to be understood, and how can they be
usefully categorized?
A very natural distinction in social science
seems to be that between economic, political, and social phenomena.
This may be slightly confusing because of
course they're all social, so what
are the differences between them, and what is specifically social (as differentiated from political or
economic)?
·
While "economic" can refer to
any method for production and distribution of goods and services, in this
context it most usefully refers to exchange in markets, based on mutual
benefit.
·
Prior to the development of markets,
there was political redistribution,
that is, based on power
relationships.
·
And previous to the rise of political
power with agriculture and cities, hunter-gatherers distributed according to tradition or custom, that is, socially, based on identity in communities.
·
(While a Robinson-Crusoe "economy"
is interesting analytically for some purposes, it collapses all three of
these into a single individual, and thus isn't very useful for social analysis.)
This simple
three-fold taxonomy of economic, political, and social phenomena seems
fundamental to the social sciences, so much so that it is often used without
explanation, seemingly unconsciously. But Kenneth Boulding
(1980, 1985, 1990), for example, explained it as follows (in reverse order
from above):
·
I can give to you or you to me, which is the basis of community, the fundamental social realm (Gudeman
2001 prefers the terms "allot" or "apportion" rather than
give).
·
I can take from you or you from me, which is the basis of government, the political realm.
·
We can exchange, which is the basis of markets, the economic
realm.
These three principles (giving, taking, and
exchanging, based respectively on identity, power, and mutuality) can be
mixed together in a variety of ways, and are perhaps never found alone and
pure. Nevertheless a wide variety of social scientists use this three-fold
categorization -- sometimes under slightly different names -- so it would
seem to represent something fundamental in our experience. Under Goodman's
(1985, pp. 79 & 81) "Principle of Objectivity" -- "Anything
which is practically real should be taken as objectively real" --
neoclassical theory must find a way to deal with the social realm.
Since the days of Adam Smith and before, economics has explored the effects of
politics and government on markets,
and to some extent it has also explored the reverse effect, of markets on
politics and government (or, at least, politics and government as a market, as in public-choice
economics).
And similarly, development economics in
particular has begun (with social-capital theory) to explore the effects of
communities and social goods on production for, and exchange in, markets.
But as noted above, the reverse effect -- of markets on
communities and on their social goods which enter the consumer's utility
function directly -- has been almost universally ignored in neoclassical
theory.
While it may be true that "social capital" plays a role in the production
and exchange of market goods and services, is it possible that markets are
otherwise "separable" from the social realm, having no reverse effects (positive or
negative) upon communities and social goods? If so, this could account for
the total absence of analysis of such effects in neoclassical discussions of
utility and welfare.
But while it is perhaps not easy to
"prove" either way, there is substantial evidence that there are
significant effects of markets on communities and social goods.
Mishan (1967-93) explored the effects of markets on communities and
social goods both anecdotally and theoretically and found substantial reason
to suspect that those effects have been significant (and not all positive).
Putnam's (1995, 2000) massive empirical study
explored many possible causes for recent social (or, more specifically,
"civic") decline in America -- many of them economic -- and finally
pinpointed three causes (the first two of which are clearly related to
markets):
·
changing living and working patterns;
·
changing consumption patterns (TV); and
·
generational change (the decline of the
generation that found comradeship in fighting World War II together).
Hirschman (1986/92)
reviewed the literature of the last 2+ centuries and came up with a four-fold
classification (below) of possible interactions between the market realm and
the social realm.
Diagram: Four possible interactions between the
market realm and the social realm
Adapted from Hirschman (1986/92, p. 136.)
It is Hirschman's
top two hypotheses we are here concerned with, especially the second, the
possibility that market effects might be negative
("self-destructive"). The first ("doux-commerce")
refers to the hypothesis that markets might improve manners and civic behavior, thus generating positive "social capital" (a possibility which
neoclassical theory also seems to ignore, though it would probably not
conflict with the usual welfare conclusions).
Plumb (1972/88) even
goes so far as to suggest that we are at the "end of an epoch". Plumb
says that our fundamental institutions (the family, religion, schools, the
city, and government) which have held us in good stead throughout the
Neolithic Epoch (since the rise of agriculture 10,000 years ago, and the rise
of cities 5,000 years ago) are being undermined at their roots, due to the
effects of science and technology (largely mediated through markets).
Thus for a variety
of theoretical and empirical reasons it would seem appropriate for
neoclassical economics to consider the effects of markets on communities and
social goods.
Any theory of markets or scarcity must include the social
realm
Markets, and even neoclassical theory about
markets (see Marwell and Ames 1981, as well as
Frank, Gilovich, and Regan 1993), seem to affect communities
and the provision of social goods, so it would seem that any thorough theory of markets would have to deal
with communities and social goods.
Similarly, social
goods are scarce, and the
communities which produce them are both scarce themselves and affected by the
scarcity of other goods (including money), so again it would seem that any
thorough theory of scarcity would
have to deal with communities and social goods.
But neoclassical
theory -- which presents itself as the
theory of scarcity, and often also assumes itself to be (and is perceived
by many as) the theory of markets
-- conveniently neglects to deal with communities or social goods (at least
not thoroughly, for example in fundamental discussions of utility and
welfare).
How has economics
managed to ignore the social realm?
Economics prides itself on tracing and elucidating all of the effects, whether direct or indirect. So it's hard to
understand how effects of scarcity and markets on communities and social
goods could have been left out.
But even those
(e.g., Johansson-Stenman 1998) who point out that
humans act in a social context -- and hence that we may need to go beyond reductionist individualism (also known as
"methodological individualism") -- often miss social goods and social utility, being usually more concerned with social capital.
Welfarism -- including individualistic or welfaristic social-welfare functions -- also comes close
to the issue of community, without quite finding it. We can accept that we
should consider only the welfare of individuals
without in any way denying the importance of the welfare of communities, because if the
communities suffer, so will the individuals. But we will have to consider the
effects of social goods on
individuals, or we will miss something of fundamental importance.
Ironically, where we
seem to finally eliminate social goods is in the restriction to the Bergson-Samuelson "social-welfare" function,
which excludes externalities (and, failing to recognize social goods, accepts
only consumption of market and public goods).
And the key is
indeed "methodological individualism", which economic sociologists Smelser and Swedberg (1994, p.
5) characterize as "the actor is uninfluenced by other actors", or,
in the words of economic anthropologists Douglas and Ney
(1998, p. 5), the actor is "a generalized human individual conceived as nonsocial or presocial".
Economist Frank
Knight (1921/40) -- who spelled out the assumption clearly and honestly --
put it this way (p. 78, italics added): "Every member of society is to
act as an individual only, in
entire independence of all other persons. To complete his [sic] independence,
he must be free from social wants, prejudices, preferences, or repulsions, or
any values which are not completely
manifested in market dealings."
What a nice simple
(or perhaps not "nice", but simple) world it would be.
Empirically it
may be difficult to include the social realm in economics
It is of course convenient
for neoclassical theory to omit communities and social goods because,
admittedly, dealing with them would be messy. Just as with many aspects of
environmental economics, communities and social goods are not easily
quantifiable. (And as environmental economics attempts to implement community-based environmental
measures, the overall results may be still harder to measure.)
But in thus being
"clean" and easily measurable, neoclassical theory is also sterile,
and sterility isn't especially attractive to students. Including communities
and the social goods derived from them in utility and welfare theory (or, to
the extent that they cannot be included, at least openly acknowledging and
discussing the implications of their omission) would make neoclassical
economics vastly more interesting to students. It would also greatly improve
the real-world applicability of any policy conclusions derived. Just as
environmental economists have taken the plunge into less easily measurable
aspects of welfare, so must we develop social
economics.
It's deceptive
not to include the social realm in economics
For economic theory to leave out communities and social goods while
presenting itself as the theory of scarcity and markets is fraudulent.
Intentionally or not, language such as the following is deceptive:
·
"social welfare", when communities
(the basic social units) -- and the social goods derived from them -- are
overlooked;
·
"complete contracting", when the fact that there are (and can
be) no contracts for social goods
is overlooked;
·
"universal markets", when the fact that there are (and can
be) no markets for social goods is
overlooked.
These and many similar usages give economic
theory an air of dishonesty (and unreality) which cannot help its public
acceptance or genuine usefulness.
Including discussion of communities and social
goods in fundamental discussions of utility and welfare could help to dispel
that air of dishonesty and unreality by alerting students and others
(including policy-makers and the ultimate consumers of policy-advice, the
general public) to the many real social issues beyond the more narrowly
"economic" ones which current theory and practice address. It would
also help to liven up the subject.
Including the
social realm is a matter of intellectual honesty and rigor
Including communities and social goods (or at least including a thorough
discussion of the consequences of their omission) in fundamental discussions
of utility, in policy recommendations about welfare, and thus in resulting public
debate, is not a matter of whether or not one "likes" (or
"believes in") markets. It's a matter of intellectual honesty, and
of -- dare I say it -- rigor.
References
Arrow, Kenneth J. (1977/83), "The organization of economic
activity: Issues pertinent to the choice of market versus nonmarket
allocation", pp. 67-81 in R. Haveman and J.
Margolis (eds.), Public Expenditure and Policy Analysis, Houghton Mifflin,
Boston.
Becker, Gary (1976), The Economic Approach to Human Behavior, University of Chicago Press.
Becker, Gary S., and Kevin M. Murphy (2000), Social Economics:
Market behavior in a social environment, Belknap/Harvard University Press.
Bell, Daniel "the younger" (1993), Communitarianism
and its Critics, Oxford University Press.
Bhaskar, Roy (1979),
The Possibility of Naturalism, Harvester Press, Brighton, Sussex.
Boadway, Robin, and
Neil Bruce (1984-93), Welfare Economics, Blackwell, Oxford, UK.
Boehm, Christopher (1999), Hierarchy in the Forest: The
evolution of egalitarian behavior, Harvard
University Press.
Boulding, Kenneth
(1980), The Social System of the Planet Earth, Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA.
Boulding, Kenneth
(1985), The World as a Total System, Sage Publications, Beverly Hills.
Boulding, Kenneth
(1990), Three Faces of Power, Sage Publications, Newbury Park.
Chwe, Michael Suk-Young (2001), Rational Ritual: Culture, coordination,
and common knowledge, Princeton University Press.
Coleman, James S. (1990-94), Foundations of Social Theory,
Harvard University Press.
Douglas, Mary, and Steven Ney (1998),
Missing Persons: A critique of the social sciences, University of California
Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles.
Etzioni, Amitai, and Oren Etzioni
(1999), "Face-to-face and computer-mediated communities, a comparative
analysis", The Information Society
15:4 (Oct.-Dec.), pp. 241-8.
Frank, Robert H., Thomas Gilovich, and
Dennis T. Regan (1993), "Does studying economics inhibit
cooperation?", Journal of Economic
Perspectives 7:2, pp. 159-71.
Fullbrook, Edward
(2001), "Real science is pluralist", Post-Autistic Economics Newsletter 5 (March),
http://www.btinternet.com/~pae_news/texts/Fullbrook1.htm
Goodman, Nicholas D. (1985), "Mathematics as an objective
science", in Thomas Tymoczko (ed.), New
Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics, Birkhaüser,
Boston.
Gudeman, Stephen
(2001), The Anthropology of Economy: Community, market, and culture,
Blackwell, Oxford.
Iannaccone, Laurence R.
(1998), "Introduction to the economics of religion", Journal of Economic Literature 36:3 (September), pp. 1465-95.
Jha, Rhagbendra (1998), Modern Public Economics, Routledge, London.
Johansson-Stenman, Olof
(1998), "On the problematic link between fundamental ethics and economic
policy recommendations", Journal
of Economic Methodology 5:2,
pp. 279-313.
Keen, Steve (2001), Debunking Economics: The naked emperor of
the social sciences, Pluto Press, Annandale, Australia.
Knight, Frank (1921/40), Risk, Uncertainty and Profit, Houghton
Mifflin, Boston.
Lewis, Thomas, Fari Amini, and Richard Lannon
(2000), A General Theory of Love, Random House, New York.
Marwell, Gerald, and
Ruth Ames (1981), "Economists free ride, does anyone else?", Journal of Public Economics 15, pp. 295-310.
Mishan, E.J. (1967-93), The Costs of Economic Growth, Weidenfeld and Nicolson,
London.
Myles, Gareth D. (1995), Public Economics, Cambridge University
Press.
Nisbet, Robert A.
(1953/70), The Quest for Community, Oxford University Press.
Pigou, A.C. (1920-32/1962), The Economics of Welfare (4th ed.),
Macmillan, London.
Plumb, J.H. (1972/88), "The end
of an epoch", in Collected Essays, Vol. I, The Making of an Historian,
University of Georgia Press, pp. 310-21 (first published in Horizon 14,
Summer 1972).
Pryor, Frederic (1977), The Origins of the Economy: A
comparative study of distribution in primitive and peasant economies,
Academic Press, New York.
Putnam, Robert (1995), "Bowling alone: America's declining
social capital", Journal of
Democracy, January (first presented in Uppsala).
Putnam, Robert (2000), Bowling Alone: The collapse and revival of
American community, Simon & Schuster, New York.
Ruhlen, Merritt
(1994), The Origin of Language: Tracing the evolution of the mother tongue,
John Wiley & Sons, New York.
Smelser, Neil J.,
and Richard Swedberg, eds. (1994), The Handbook of
Economic Sociology, Princeton University Press.
Sober, Elliott, and David Sloan Wilson (1998), Unto Others: The
evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior,
Harvard University Press.
Walras, Leon
(1874), Elements of Pure Economics [the (1954) William Jaffe translation of
the (1926) édition définitive of Éléments d'économie politique pure: ou, Théorie de la
richesse sociale, Allen & Unwin, London.
Wright, Robert (1994), The Moral Animal: Evolutionary psychology
and everyday life, Pantheon Books, New York.
|