Post-Autistic Economics Network
More Student
Essays
Home Page
PAE
Review
|
www.paecon.net
Student Essays on Post-Autistic Economics
posted April 2003
Is there a chance for the dismal science to become more
cheerful?
Some reflections on the prospects of PAE
Andreas Reinstaller (PhD
candidate, MERIT, University of Maastricht, Netherlands)
Abstract
The Post-Autistic Economics
movement has triggered a welcome and much needed discussion about the
relevance of contemporary mainstream economics, but the question is how
relevant Post-Autistic Economics will actually be to the future course of the
dismal science. This essay suggests that there is still a long way to go
until any alternative school of thought will be a true alternative to the
mainstream in economic teaching and research.
Introduction: Economics as a positive
science
Economists, like any other scientist, need a systematic
body of knowledge to organise their thinking. But is there a coherent body of
knowledge for heterodox economists? Among them there is much agreement of
what economics should not be (i.e. it should not be Neoclassical) but much
less of what economics ought to be. For sure all heterodox economists agree
that economics should not just study the outcome of allocation decisions by
rational actors. Perhaps there is some common ground that economics should study
the economy as a process and that accordingly economics should be historical,
but I fear in many cases that's it. And not even on this idea all of
heterodox economists would agree. Different schools have a different scope
and also differentiated ideas on the relevant economic factors to study, and
even within one heterodox label one finds several schools of thought. So,
under the heading Post-Keynesian Economics one finds grouped a very
heterogeneous bunch consisting of Kaleckians,
monetary Post-Keynesians, Kaldorians,
Post-Keynesian Marxists and sometimes even Neo-Ricardians.
I have not found a treatise successfully endeavouring to present something
like a unified approach to Post-Keynesian Economics. Similar dilemmas are to
be found in other heterodox schools. The case of Evolutionary economics is
discussed below.
Neo-classical economics as an unrivalled box of tools
The result of the Babylonian chaos in heterodoxy is that there is no
clear box of tools available to the graduate student that could be taught in
a doctoral coursework, and applied without having headaches regards to the
consistency of the framework one chooses to use. Neo-Classical economists
consider their framework being rigorous as they claim it draws all its
conclusions out of one idealised model of human behaviour. This
model is at the centre of never ending debates about its empirical relevance
and its philosophical as well as theoretical implications, and heterodox
economists agree that it is not the right one. What on the other hand is true
beyond doubt is, that its ever adaptive character gives to the practitioners
of mainstream economics a routinised way of
producing theory that is unequalled. A clear reference model, with clear
categories and concepts is given, where a set of convexity conditions on
production and preference sets and the postulated existence of atomistically competitive markets for all extant and
contingent commodities guarantees the existence of a Pareto optimal
equilibrium. Taking that as a starting point one may define a household
through a "well behaved" utility function, do the same for the
firm, derive equilibrium conditions and do some comparative statics, reformulate the problem in a dynamic context
etc. It is clear to the theorist how the economic problem has to be
addressed, and no discussion ensues whether a linear homogeneous production
function of the Neo-Classical type is the right analytical framework to
address problems of aggregate growth, or whether a utility function really
reflects human preferences. Of course that's what heterodox people detest,
but that's also what makes the Neo-Classics' strength. Shall we believe that
90% of our colleagues are thus simple minded? Not at all. Some just have
never heard about the capital controversy or Bourdieu's
theory of social distinction, and anyhow after having spent years in trying
to master Hamiltonians they're just locked in. Others are just tired of never
ending debates with no clear cut outcome, and others again can't see a forest
with all the different sorts of trees standing around.
The heterogeneity of heterodoxy: the Babylonic dimension of evolutionary economics
Let's take the example of Evolutionary economics. The interested
student may ask at first what makes it different from the stuff he or she
have been taught in undergraduate days? But one finds, that this is not easy
to answer. So let two distinguished scholars in the field answer the
question:
"Sometimes it is barely distinguishable from the very
notion of dynamics itself, cum some non-linearities
and phase transitions. Elsewhere, it takes a meaning much nearer to that in
biological theories involving selection, inheritance and variation. In yet
other perspectives, it borrows only part of the biological view,
significantly modified to suit the distinctive features of socio-economic
processes.", Dosi and Winter [2], p.1.
And they
continue, that "notwithstanding possible differences in other more
substantive hypotheses, evolutionary theories share the methodological
imperative “dynamics first !” (ibid. p.2). The subject matter of
evolutionary economics seems to be close to Classical economics, as these
different approaches "aim at the interpretation of economic phenomena at
different levels of aggregation - including industrial dynamics and macroeconomics
growth" (ibid., p. 7). Aggregate growth is driven by technical advances
which depend on technological opportunities, the ease of imitation of new
technical discoveries, the competitive situation and the way firms process
technological knowledge. This would typically overlap with the agenda of
Classical economics, with the treatment of income distribution missing.
But what are the precise categories and concepts of
Evolutionary economics? What are the "differences in substantive
hypotheses"? Dosi and Winter list a series of
different approaches ranging from post-Schumpeterian studies à la Nelson and Winter [4] over evolutionary game theory
to artificial economies (op. cit. p.2). It is not quite clear what that means
methodologically, but remember "dynamics first". Let us examine
briefly two different approaches that would perfectly fit this maxim. Stanley
Metcalfe has developed a series of evolutionary models over the years and
recently a comprehensive framework of industry development [6], which is
quite representative for one stream in Evolutionary thinking. This model
connects the distribution of heterogeneous firms to the growth of an
industry, and presents the mechanisms that account for this dynamics. This
mechanism is the replicator, that ensures - in a
simplified way - that more profitable firms dominate less profitable ones and
drive them out of the industry. A classical case of "big fish eats small
fish", and a principle that would make regulators prick up their ears.
The replicator principle tells us that there is a
natural tendency to monopoly in an industry, even though the causes for the
dominance may be manifold and a monopoly may perhaps never emerge. This
result comes without any model of individual behaviour. The model together with
related literature on technological regimes and technological variety imply,
that sometimes it may be wise to intervene in the development of an industry.
This is a possible policy implication coming with the use of the replicator principle. The box of tools lies in the realm
of Dynamic Systems Theory, and fulfils the postulate of "dynamics
first".
Another branch of dynamic models comes also under the
Evolutionary heading. These are stochastic network models where agents acting
on the market discover slice by slice - through local spillovers
from their neighbours on the lattice - the state of the world. Some common
knowledge distribution or behaviour emerges which has some small probability
to show phase transitions. The most important proposition in this type of
models is that individuals do not act independently from each other and that
they act boundedly rational. Typically statistical
mechanics methods (like Ising models) are used here
(e.g. Weisbuch et al. [7]), even though they do not
precisely fit the evolutionary paradigm. They borrow from physics and not
from evolutionary biology, but they are explicitly dynamic, and even better,
they are stochastic. The view is of the economy as a self-organising system,
where agents gradually discovery their surroundings. This resembles the
Austrian position (see Hayek [3]) on the competition process quite a bit, and
with that comes also a similar view on policy: intervention in the market
most likely distorts the real information available and hence no intervention
should take place. For instance, if economic agents trade information on
several designs of a technological innovation government intervention -
considered as a global information externality - may lead to premature
convergence to one dominant instead of a variety of designs, which may have a
better welfare profile. This is of course in some contrast to the
implications from replicator dynamics. In
"Evolutionary" economics, it seems, everything goes as long as the
maxim "dynamics first" is not violated.
Conclusion
Schumpeter [6] conceded that economic reasoning might well be
ideologically biased, but that it was the value free box of tools an
economist had at hand, that saved economics from the dim prospect of not
having the right of being considered "precise" at an equal footing
of natural sciences. Of course this is an illusion and Maurice Dobb [1] has clearly underscored the futility of any
attempt to declare economics a positive science by simply referring to the
box of analytical tools available. Economics may thus well be a positive
science, but its results will never be free of normative implications. This
is particularly clear in the example given above. But how is it possible that
two such distinct views on policy can emerge? I believe it has to do with the
casuistic way on how assumptions are brought into Evolutionary models.
Unluckily the messy situation I find Evolutionary economics in is not
uncommon in other heterodox schools. I guess there is a long way to go until
anything competitive to Neo-Classical Economics can emerge. More efforts to
integrate the different approaches and develop clear common categories are
needed, otherwise heterodox approaches will continue not to be a viable
alternative to orthodoxy.
Cited works
[1] Maurice Dobb (1973). Theories
of value and distribution since Adam Smith : ideology and economic theory.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[2] Giovanni Dosi
and Sydney G. Winter (2000). Interpreting Economic Change:
Evolution, Structures and Games. Siena: LEM
Working Paper No. 2000/08.
[3] Friedrich August von Hayek (1937). Economics
and Knowledge. Economica, 4(NS), 33-54.
[4] Richard R. Nelson and Sydney G. Winter
(1982). An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
[5] J. Stanley METCALFE (1998). Evolutionary
Economics and Creative Destruction. London: Routledge.
[6] J.A.
Schumpeter (1946). History of Economic Analysis. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, reprint 1994
by Routledge, London.
[7] Gerard Weisbuch, Alan Kirman, and Dorothea Herreiner (2000).
Market Organisation and Trading Relationships. The Economic
Journal, 110, 411-436.
___________________________________
e-mail: a.reinstaller@merit.unimaas.nl
|