|
sanity, humanity and science post-autistic economics review(formerly
“newsletter”) Issue
no. 13; May 2,
2002
back
issues at www.paecon.net subscribers
in over 120 countries latest economic
journalism at GEN Subscriptions are free, To subscribe, email
"subscribe". To unsubscribe, email "unsubscribe".
To subscribe
In this issue: - Yanis Varoufakis Why Critics of Economics Can
Ill-afford the “Postmodern Turn” - Alex Millmow An IgNobel Scandal - Geoff Harcourt Comment
on Guerrien’s Essay - Bruce
J. Caldwell In Defense of Basic Economic Reasoning - Jacques Sapir Response
to Guerrien’s Essay - Gilles Raveaud For Guerrien… and Beyond - Poul Thøis Madsen Teaching
students of political science post-autistic economics - Helge Peukert Review
of Intersubjectivity in Economics Some
recent articles on PAE Editor’s
Note: Five of the articles in this issue are in part or in Why Critics of Economics Can
Ill-afford the “Postmodern Turn” The dissident’s nightmareIt is a sad irony when the activities of dissidents help
shore up the establishment they set out to subvert. The point of this piece
is to warn the ‘economic’ dissident: Beware the Postmodern Turn! The argument will turn on
the thought that postmodern criticisms of economics
serve the twin purpose of (a) releasing pent-up frustration with the
profession while, at once, (b) reinforcing its ideological backbone. Every era has a tendency surreptitiously to guide young
dissidents toward a specific ‘umbrella movement’; one that ends
up shaping their milieu. Existentialism, structuralism, neo-Marxism, etc.
have given their place, in our era of devalued political goods, to Postmodernity and Deconstruction. Without wishing to
discuss the ‘postmodern condition’
generally, I shall concentrate entirely on its likely effects on the struggle
to ‘civilise’ economics. In this regard, the problem with postmodern thinking is that it stands no chance of
success. Postmodernity’s
criticism of grandiose Theory may be terribly satisfying to those who adopt
its grandiose pronouncements. However, the satisfaction at having lambasted
all Theory is momentary and the ensuing subversion short-lived. To paraphrase
Marx, the subverters will be, eventually, subverted
and, tragically, the neoclassical establishment will come out stronger and
better equipped to obfuscate social reality than ever before.2 If
I am right, the task of the PAE movement must be to
clear the way for radical criticism that avoids the postmodern
trap as resolutely as it opposes economic autism. Dissidents or the economists’ handmaidens?Modernity marginalised Religion, but retained religious transcendence by worshipping Theory. Economics emerged as the highest form of this secular creed and enchanted all of its practitioners; free-marketeer and protectionist, liberal and Marxist, Keynesian and monetarist. It now seems that some economists are breaking ranks; joining the ‘other’, the postmodern, side which defines itself in anti-theoretical tones that exude an atheist’s anti-religious fervour. The danger is that the legitimate anger of students (which has given rise to the PAE movement) will draw them to an apostasy without a future. For despite its considerable oeuvre, postmodern criticisms of economics are doomed to shrivel and be absorbed by mainstream economics; the predator turning into unsuspecting prey. I risk this prediction for two reasons. First, postmodernists allow economics to parade as equally
scientific as the natural sciences (albeit on the grounds that no
discipline is truly scientific). They are right of course to think that all
theory resembles religion, since it also seeks to give meaning to the practices
and expectations of whole communities. However some theories are capable of
transcending religion and approaching objectivity better than others.
Nature’s habit of working independently of our beliefs about it means
that the natural scientist can devise experiments which have the power
disinterestedly to discard falsity and thus forge knowledge and progress.
Society, on the other hand, is corrupted to the very marrow of its bones by
our collective beliefs about it, and can therefore provide no objective test
of social theory (the latter being part of the very web of beliefs that
society is made of). Thus social theory, unlike thermodynamics, is condemned
to remain untestable, and stuck in the realm of
opinion. Economics valiantly attempts to extricate itself from this fate with
a touching commitment to mathematics but, sadly, it only ends up as a
religion with equations. Postmodernity errs in
thinking of this as the inevitable failure of all Modernist enterprises. It
lambastes economists’ churlish reliance on an Outer Wall of Algebra and
an Inner Wall of Statistics but overlooks their success at never even
coming close to the nature and the dynamics of contemporary capitalism, thus
shielding the latter from rational criticism. But such is the fate of all
idealisms which give language an existence independent of the material
conditions of social life and reproduction. If only postmodernist critics
understood theology and mathematics a little better! Perhaps they would have
recognised in economics the greatest proof that Modernity is saturated with
its negation. Which brings me to the second part of the argument: Postmodernity not only lets neoclassical economics off
the hook but, more worryingly, reinforces it copiously before dissolving into
it. Consider what the postmodern rejection of metanarratives means at the individual level: It means
the loss of any capacity to scrutinise one’s private urges
rationally on the basis of some collectively constructed notion (or metanarrative) of the Good. Stripped of those capacities,
the individual fragments into a community of selves, a bundle of ordinal
preferences, and ends up with no one self whose preferences those are.
In this Empire of Ordinal Preference the only possible
data that social theory can go to work with are the differences in individual
whims and freely chosen identities. These data are then, courtesy of their
ordinal properties, impossible to compare across persons (for this would
require a metanarrative) or procure a view of
capitalism as a system. Thus in a fully-fledged postmodern
schema, social relations are confined to interplay, voluntarism, tolerance
and exchange; society is the playground where the latter unfold; and
discussions of the General Will, exploitation and developmental freedom make
no sense. Does this all sound familiar? If it does the reason is that neoclassical economics went
down that alley decades ago. The asymptotic limit of postmodern
fragmentation is the neoclassical general equilibrium economic model.
Both Neoclassicism and Postmodernity espouse a
radical egalitarianism which is founded on the rejection of any standard or
value by which either individual action or the institutions of late
capitalism (e.g. the labour and capital markets) can be subjected to rational
criticism. In short, whereas the problem with modernist mechanism was that
its view of our world excluded value from the outset, the problem with Postmodernity is that it ends up having no view of the
world and becomes easy-pickings for a similarly viewless/valueless tradition,
one which bears the additional weaponry of intricate mathematics and endless
econometric ‘evidence’. For Oscar Wilde the supreme vice was shallowness. For Postmodernity it is the New Jerusalem. Its playfulness
allowed it to thrive in the friendlier waters of literary and cultural
studies at a time when ‘margins’ were becoming central and
classical stuffiness was going out of fashion. But now postmodernists have
entered shark-infested territory. Neoclassical economics, another purveyor of
shallowness, threatens to bend them to its will,3 gain strength
from them and subsequently reinforce hierarchies more oppressive and
totalising than those the postmodernists set out initially to dismantle. When the IMF dictates its policies to some hapless Third World country, there is a strong whiff of the radical egalitarianism shared equally between general equilibrium and Postmodernity. The same whiff accompanies, and legitimises, the inexorable devaluation of political goods, the vulgar commodification of human bodies and values, the impossibility of conceptualising freedom-from-the-market, the depiction of Central Banks as ‘independent’ only when under the thumb of financial capital, the confusion of liberty with the freedom to exploit and to demean and, above all else, the portrayal of coercion as tâtonnement. Thus Postmodernity unwittingly blows fresh wind in the sails of neoclassicism, the undisputed champion of the deconstructed human agent. While warning us correctly that new authoritarianisms will be born when we get caught up in our own rhetoric, it offers no resistance to the current authoritarianism of neoclassical economics and, more so, the socio-economic system that it serves. Conclusion: The dissidents’ dilemma When a fresh wave of criticism is unleashed, it picks up
along the way pre-existing discontents, hitherto bopping along hopelessly
near the surface, and propels them toward the shores of exposure and
respectability. Lonely dissidents suddenly find a new ‘movement’
that will have them. New hope of escaping obscurity is thus born. In recent years many dissident voices had to adapt
themselves to postmodern-speak in an attempt to be
‘included’ on the postmodern bandwagon.
The PAE movement must release such voices from this
obligation. Social criticism of economics must reclaim an awareness that to
reject the scientific status of economics is not to reject science in general
or to espouse postmodernism. Indeed irony and ambiguity were utilised, long before Postmodernity, by thinkers eager to come to what a more
confident past once knew as the truth. To re-establish irony, ambiguity and
indeterminateness in the discourse of economists would be a triumph of the
spirit. But it would not be a postmodern turn. For
the latter has no monopoly on an appreciation of the radical indeterminacy of
social processes (as Hegel would be all to eager to remind us) or the
importance of not taking our selves, and our theories, too seriously. On the
contrary, Postmodernity undermines itself by offering
Modernity’s most awful purveyor another means of extending its
dominance. So, we have arrived at the dissident’s dilemma. The postmodern kernel within neoclassical economics forces a
stark choice: Submit to homo economicus and
model our messy world’s dynamic as if a series of suburban disputes
between postmodern neighbours. Or, seek an
historically grounded understanding of how systematic patterns of power and
economics are the joint products of the continual feedback between
technological developments and evolving social formations. The difference
between the two options is not theoretical; it is ideological. The postmodern turn will be chosen by pseudo-dissidents whose
prime interests lie in acquiring a chic image; one that the self-effacing postmodern criticism is good at imparting. The less
fashionable option of working towards historically grounded knowledge will
appeal to the truly ‘unreasonable’ dissidents; those driven by an
unbending commitment to a rational transformation of society. Notes
1. Department of Economics, University of Athens, 8 Pesmazoglou Street, Athens 10596 and Department of
Economics, University of Sydney, Sydney, Australia. Email: yanisv@econ.uoa.gr 2. Recently, Routledge published
a volume on the nexus of Postmodernity with economics
edited by Jack Amariglio, Stephen Cullenberg, and David Ruccio
(2001). The following thoughts have been extracted from my review of that
book (forthcoming in the Journal of Economic Methodology) 3. Courtesy of a more sophisticated take on the same type
of philosophical shallowness. References Cullenberg, S., J. Amariglio and D. Ruccio (2001).
Postmodernity, Economics and Knoweldge, London and New York: Routledge Varoufakis, Y.
(2002). ‘Deconstructing Homo Economicus?’,
Journal of Economic Methodology, forthcoming. _______________________________________ Yanis Varoufakis’ most recent book is Foundations
of Economics : A Beginner's Companion. SUGGESTED
CITATION: An IgNobel Scandal In his play ‘The Importance of Being Earnest’
Oscar Wilde said of political economy that ‘even these metallic
problems have their melodramatic side’. That prophecy came true at this
year’s Academy awards. Apart from the Nobel Prize and the Oscar almost
melting into one with the fanfare meted out to the film ‘A Beautiful
Mind’, there was a whiff of scandal with Russell Crowe missing out on a
best actor award for his portrayal of John Nash Jr.
even though the production did well in all the other major award categories.
Nash, who was in the audience remarked that, like the Nobel Prize, there was
an element of politics in the Awards. Indeed there was, and not just because
Nash himself was a bit lucky to win the Nobel Prize with the Prize-bestowing
committee barely convinced about the wisdom of giving it to a schizophrenic
mathematician. As Sylvia Nasar, author of A
Beautiful Mind shows, the committee reluctantly came round to the
chairman Assar Lindbeck’s
view that Nash should be given the award, as Russell Crowe, aka John Nash, put it in a southern drawl, for his
‘one truly original idea’.
It is often overlooked too that Nash actually shared the Nobel Prize
in Economic Science with two mathematical economists, namely John Harsanyi and Reinhard Selten. The fact
that the economics community bestowed the prize upon Nash tells us something
about what that profession adores, namely, a mathematically driven formalism
that basically reduces to second-guessing your rival’s gameplan. Ironically, Nash has openly stated that he is not really
an economist. But there is, in all this, an even greater controversy in the
Nobel Prize in Economics. It concerns the great English economist, Joan
Robinson, who died nearly twenty years ago. Apparently she died lamenting
that she was never given the gong. This might come as a surprise because it
is alleged that Robinson made clear to the committee that she did not want to
be considered for the accolade. An alternative version is that she much
preferred ‘having a grievance’ in not being awarded the prize. It
was a mark of distinction not to be given the award. She would, moreover, have been horrified to
be awarded the prize in company with someone with polar views to herself as
had occurred in 1974 when the Economics Nobel Prize was, in an ideological
balancing act, shared by the Austrian economist, FA Hayek, and the Swedish
institutional economist, Gunnar Myrdal.
When Milton Friedman was awarded the 1976 Nobel Prize, Myrdal
spat the dummy and embarrassed the committee for its overly political
decision with a string of denunciations, not least about the merits of having
a prize for economic science. The stormy petrel of Cambridge economics spent most of her
life trying to undermine the pillars of neoclassical thought and replacing it
with a new critical economy. She failed in that endeavour, but as her bête noire, Paul Samuelson, conceded,
Robinson was a pioneering theorist in so many fields that she deserved the
gong. In 1975 there was immense
speculation that Robinson was to be honoured. It was, after all, the
International Year of the Woman and there was no more outstanding candidate
than Robinson. The gossip in the economics profession was that Robinson was a
shoo–in for the prize (McCarty, 2000) To much surprise the Nobel Prize
committee overlooked her and continued to do so right up to her death in
1983. To borrow a journalistic cliché, Joan Robinson became, at the stroke of
a committee chairman’s pen, the
best Nobel Prize winner we never had. It is said that sunk costs do not
matter, but that decision has cost the profession dear, since surely having
not one female in the pantheon of economic laureates does little to inspire
one half of the student population to do a major in economics. How could she have been overlooked? Milton Friedman felt
she was ‘blackballed’ because of espousal of Keynesianism and
that it had nothing to do with gender (Feldman, 2000). Arguably it could have
been due to her works which were mostly destructive of conventional economic
theory and therefore, in the committee eyes, nothing to really build on. Nor
was her methodology of the ilk befitting a true deterministic science. It seems however that Lindbeck,
the powerful chairman of the Nobel economics committee was more concerned
that the cantankerous Robinson would use the prize to attack mainstream economics
or, even worse, publicly refuse it, especially, if awarded for her earlier
work, The Theory of Imperfect Competition which she had
disowned. Unlike many other Prize-winners, Robinson had more than just
‘one big thing’ to hang her fame on. The consensus was that
Robinson would, either way, be too risky. For a while perhaps it helped her
cause to establish a more heterodox economics. However, the award of the
Nobel prize to a self-confessed left wing Keynesian would have given the
Post-Keynesian movement weight as a viable alternative to the mainstream. In the case of Nash, the Nobel Prize committee sent
someone to check to make sure he was no longer receiving messages from
extraterrestrials. If the same courtesy had been extended to Robinson in
1982, they would have found her amenable to the idea of getting the award.
According to Juliet Schor, a professor of sociology
at Boston University who looked after Robinson while she did a semester of
guest teaching at Williams in 1982, the grande dame of economics was
‘terribly disappointed’ not to have won that year’s Nobel
economics prize. Adding insult to injury it went to another Chicago economist
and arch polemicist, George Stigler, for his work on deregulation. Robinson
apparently desperately wanted to win not so much for the recognition but for
the million dollars that came with it. She intended to donate it to the peace
movement. One could, therefore, liken Robinson’s experience to all
those great films and superb acting performances that missed out on an Oscar.
However even mainstream economists agree that even in Robinson’s time
all the titans of the profession have been deservedly rewarded bar her.
Whatever the truth behind the failure of Joan Robinson to be honoured by the
committee it remains the most mystifying incident in the history of the
awards. Mark Blaug,
a conservative historian of economic thought has no doubt that
Robinson’s omission from the list of Nobel laureates is ‘one of
the most extraordinary acts of academic vindictiveness... in recorded
intellectual history’ (1985). And, like the Oscars, the Nobel Prize
cannot be given posthumously to repair the damage. References
Blaug M.
(1985) Great Economists since Keynes Edward Elgar
: Cheltenham Feldman B. (2000) The Nobel Prize Arcade publishing:
New York McCarty M.H. (2001) The Nobel
Laureates McGraw-Hill: New York Nasar S.
(2002) A Beautiful Mind : Faber and Faber SUGGESTED
CITATION: Comment on Bernard Guerrien’s
Essay May I comment on
Bernard Guerrien's essay in
Issue 12, March 15, 2002 in which he has some disagreement with what he
alleges I argued in Issue 11? There I
set out what I think is happening in modern mainstream microeconomic theory,
for example, that the general equilibrium model is the basis for descriptive
analysis of competitive markets instead of being at best, as is
conceded by the most thoughtful general equilibrium theorists, e.g. Frank
Hahn, a reference point. Guerrien says I agree with this. If he had any knowledge at all about what I
have argued for many years now, he would not have advanced such a
canard. In fact, as with Joan
Robinson, I do not even accept the distinction between micro and macro as
valid or useful; and I have doubts about whether general equilibrium is a
reference point and certainly it is not descriptive analysis. I also tend to
think that game theory may not be that much use in thinking about
non-competitive market structures. But
I am re-examining this long held view, following re-reading Ken Arrow’s
masterful obituary of John Harsanyi and his
contributions (Economic Journal, 111, 2001, F747-52). Minds should never be closed even in your
71st year! (I do not know
how old Bernard Guerrien is.) Guerrien quibbles with my (implicit)
description of Akerlof, Spender and Stiglitz’s findings as “new”, arguing
that they are just presenting some very old ideas in a mathematical
form. He is right about the latter;
but then I never claimed the findings were new. Mainstream economists think it is helpful
to establish rigorously by maths, if at all possible, the arguments for
conjectures, old and new. I think that
there is a limited place for this approach in economics. Moreover, if it helps to illuminate the
understanding of people who find thinking in this way useful, no harm is
done, provided that this way of proceeding is not regarded as the only
way of proceeding, and its advocates do not insist on a monopoly. I argued this in my first essay in this
review (issue 6)
(and in many other places). Finally, Amartya Sen is a real force for
good in our discipline and the award of the Nobel Prize to him is a positive
signal, to be embraced, not belittled. SUGGESTED
CITATION: In Defense of Basic Economic ReasoningBruce J. Caldwell (University of North Carolina, US) In issue number 12 of the Post-Autistic Economics
Review, Bernard Gurrien poses the provocative
question, “Is There Anything Worth Keeping in Standard
Microeconomics?” His answer
seems to be, “Not much.” Gurrien
complains about the highly formalized nature of modern microeconomic theory,
about the use of assumptions that describe neither the world nor the actions
of the people that populate it. He
finds much formal theory useless and irrelevant for helping us to understand
how the world works. I agree with many of Gurrien’s
criticisms of formal, highly mathematicized
microeconomic theory. I disagree, though, with his conclusion that the
irrelevance of the theory undermines microeconomics. In my opinion, there is a body of economic
reasoning, something that might be called “basic economic reasoning”
that can and should be separated out from what might be called “formal
microeconomic theory.” Much of
basic economic reasoning is in fact microeconomic in nature, but it preceded
the latter temporally in terms of its development and it does not depend on
formal economic theory for its validity or usefulness. It is my contention
that basic economic reasoning is truly important. My fear is that if we take Gurrien’s advice, we will throw out the standard
economic reasoning “baby” with the formal economic theory
“bathwater.” I will elaborate on these claims by citing some personal
examples. In recent years I have taught both a one semester “everything
you want to know about economics” course as well as the principles of
microeconomics course to American undergraduates. I use very little
mathematics in either course. With the exception of a little algebra for
calculating elasticities, all other concepts are
handled graphically, with production possibilities curves and supply and
demand diagrams being the chief graphical tools employed. Even with this
elementary set of tools, by the end of the course students have learned a lot
about how the world works. Their education is a practical one, one that
allows them to read a paper better and to understand economic issues that are
discussed in the news. Of course what
I am doing in the classroom is not unique; many other economists do the same
things in their own principles courses. Basically, I use the graphs to tell stories about the
world. The graphs alone are useless without the stories, and similarly, the
stories lose all focus without the graphs. So, for example, in discussing
price fixing we use a supply and demand diagram to distinguish between price
ceilings and price supports. When
price ceilings are binding, one can expect to see excess demand, or
shortages, and one also often encounters such things as non-price rationing,
deterioration in product quality, and black markets. With these general
concepts, we can them explore such diverse phenomena as rent controls in New
York City, black markets for tickets to the theater
and sporting events, the use of ration coupons during times of war, lines at
gasoline stations in the U.S. in the 1970s (when gas prices were controlled),
and the ubiquitous lines that one used to observe in East Bloc countries
under communism. The price support diagram is useful for analyzing current
policies (like agricultural price supports or the minimum wage law) as well
as those that have been proposed (comparable worth policies). Once the concept of elasticities
has been introduced, the diagrams can be used to analyze everything from the
incidence of taxation to the “paradox of plenty” in agriculture
(good growing seasons can lead to a reduction in farmer’s revenues if
demand for their product is inelastic) to the reason why a successful
“War on Drugs” that managed to reduce the supply of illegal drugs
would put more revenue into the pockets of drug dealers. (If the demand for
drugs is inelastic, a rise in the price of drugs causes a less than
proportionate fall in quantity demanded, so total revenue increases.) Production possibilities curves can be used
whenever the discussion focuses on opportunity costs and the necessity of
making trade-offs. Basic economic reasoning and simple diagrams can also be
used to tell stories that go beyond economics to what might be called
political economy. The recent history of agricultural price supports in the
U.S. provides numerous insights into how politics and economics interact. In
1996 a law was passed that was supposed to gradually phase out agricultural
price supports, so that they would be gone by 2002. In order to induce farm
interests to accept the law, payments in the initial years were quite
generous. But as we got closer and closer to 2002, and prices for
agricultural products began falling (this was exactly what was supposed to
happen, of course), farm interests declared a “crisis” in their
industry. For the past few years, “emergency” farm legislation
was passed by Congress to help agricultural interests survive their
“crises.” The recurring
crises have in turn prompted calls for a “comprehensive” farm
bill to deal with the problems on a permanent basis. And sure enough, after
September 11 some have begun referring to the new proposed legislation as a
Farmland Security Bill. A few years ago, a dot.com at the end of a company
name was supposed to ensure that investors would love it. Now in Congress
putting the word “Security” into a bill’s name will help to
ensure its speedy passage.
Many other examples could be given. The recent decision by
the Bush administration to place tariffs of about 30% on steel imports was
analyzed in one newspaper under the wonderful byline,
“In Big Steel States, the Bush Democrat May Be Born.” Ohio, West Virginia and Pennsylvania are
major steel-producing states, and the outcome of mid-term elections there may
be crucial in deciding who controls the Congress. So again steel has gotten
help, even though it is one of the most protected of all American industries:
past studies have estimated that it costs American consumers about $750,000
(in terms of higher prices paid) for every steelworker’s job saved.
That number will need to be updated in the light of this recent event,
especially given that other nations have begun retaliating with tariffs of
their own that will further raise the prices that consumers face. Though basic economic reasoning is simple, it is not
simplistic, and indeed, it often leads one to results that are not at all
obvious. For example, the idea that the incidence of taxation depends on the elasticities of supply and demand, and not on whether a
tax is initially paid by a buyer or a seller of a good, is not at all
intuitive, but is crucial if one wants to understand who actually bears the
burden of a tax. Similarly, the idea that there can be gains from trade even
when one country has an absolute advantage in the production of goods –
the fundamental idea of comparative advantage – is not one that many
non-economists have mastered. Some will say that basic economic reasoning is not valid
because it rests on faulty foundations – one must assume that agents
are perfectly rational, with complete information, trading in perfectly
competitive markets to get its results. This simply confuses formal
mathematical theory with basic economic reasoning. In my opinion, basic economic reasoning
does not depend on formal microeconomic theory for its validity. Now, to be sure, economists have not been
very good at identifying just what it does depend on. That is a topic for
economic methodology, and over the years various contending views have been
advanced. My own intuition is that there may well be multiple
“foundations” that help to explain why different parts of the
theory may work. In any event, my own confidence in basic economic reasoning
has less to do with the fact that I know why it works, then with the fact
that it does work: as my examples hopefully demonstrate, it can prove to be
extremely useful in organizing and understanding various and often very
diverse social phenomena. The proof of the pudding is in the eating, and in
this regard basic economic reasoning seems to me to provide much upon which
to feast. There will of course be the complaint of those who believe
that basic economic reasoning is simply ideology dressed up as science. For them, to say that “we live in a
world in which scarcity makes choice necessary” is an ideological
statement; or to assert that “producing goods for which one has a
comparative advantage permits gains from trade” is a not-so-covert defense of globalization; and so on. To this I would reply that I think of the
statements of basic economic reasoning as being positive rather than
normative claims. (This is not to say that they are easily testable claims.)
I would further rejoin that those who think that basic economic reasoning is
simply a defense of capitalism should look once
again at the socialist calculation debate, and in particular at the positions
articulated by the defenders of market socialism, or for those who would like
to go back further, at the Austrian economist Friedrich von Wieser’s Natural Value. These economists
recognized that an understanding of economic reasoning was necessary even if
one was in favor of organizing a socialist economy.
As one wag put it on the recent television production of the book Commanding
Heights, ignoring how markets operate is much like ignoring the winds and
the tides – you do so at your peril. In conclusion, I join with Bernard Gurrien
in lamenting the turn of the profession towards microeconomic models of ever
increasing formal complexity. Explaining why the profession has gone down
this road is something that has increasingly captured the attention of (our
ever diminishing number, alas, of) historians of economic thought. But we
should not conclude that microeconomics is of no value. Basic economic
reasoning was there before the advent of such modeling,
and it remains a powerful tool today for understanding how the world works. ______________________________ Bruce Caldwell is the author of Beyond
Positivism : Economic Methodology in the Twentieth Century. SUGGESTED
CITATION: Response to Guerrien’s
Essay Jacques Sapir (L'École des Hautes Études
en Sciences Sociales, Paris) Bernard Guerrien's provocative
paper in PAE Review no. 12 raises some important
issues. Along with other heterodoxical French economists
I am greatly indebted to Guerrien’s
frequently illuminating work about neoclassical economics. However, I feel
that this particularly recent contribution was ill-conceived and perhaps
pointless. I agree with Guerrien that
standard microeconomic assumptions are not relevant. I too criticized them in my Les Trous Noirs
de la Science Économique. In addition, I agree
that the Arrow-Debreu model has nothing to do with
a decentralized economy. However, part of Guerrien’s
argument reveals an unhelpful bias against abstraction itself. One of
Spinoza’s famous arguments is helpful here. Spinoza taught us that the concept of dog
doesn't bark nor bite but the concept of dog is nevertheless necessary to
understand a world where real dogs can do both. Guerrien’s
misplaced bias against abstraction is very clear when he states that Akerlof, Spence and Stiglitz
have no new findings and have simply restated old ideas. Actually what these
Nobel Prize winners did was to restate certain ideas at a higher level of abstraction. To return to Spinoza’s argument, real
dogs may have predated the concept of dog, but such a concept was still
necessary and useful in the development of human culture. Unfortunately, the
way Guerrien orients his quest for reality throws
us back to the nomilaism which pertained pre-Ockham. In addition, rejecting Stiglitz's
contribution to the future demise of the current orthodoxy in economics, be
it his theoretical one or his political economy one, will not help to achieve
the needed breakthrough. The PAE movement would
probably not have been possible without Stiglitz’s
theoretical and political work in the last decade. To acknowledge the positive effect of Stiglitz's
work does not mean agreeing to accept it as offering the limits to change. What
is needed is a shift from the information paradigm - plainly positivist - to
a new knowledge paradigm. The best way to move forward on this path is
probably to destroy, step by step, old microeconomics, and not just to forget
them. We now have the possibility of opposing new arguments to every argument
voiced by the neoclassical traditionalists. This is particularly true when we
compare the traditional way of thinking about individual preferences to what
we have learnt during the last two decades (Slovic's
preference reversal or Tversky's framing
effect). It is also true of our
thinking about rationality and, last but not least, about the necessary of
making a distinction between signals and information. Actually the information Stiglitz is so fond of does not exist as such. Information is always a processed signal,
which means that knowledge predates information and that knowledge is at the center of the paradigm, not information. And don't think
that this is just a matter of terminology.
If we acknowledge the centrality of knowledge, then trying to collect
as many signals as possible can be as detrimental to decision-making as being
starved of information. Increasing
competition, which is Stiglitz's cure for most of
our problems, would then mean a considerable increase in signal gathering
that could overwhelm our signal processing ability and lead to bad decisions
and imperfect resources allocation. It is probably important for me to state explicitly that I
do not belong to the methodological individualism school. I think we have to
reclaim holism but in a non-deterministic framework. To understand that the
individual agent is part of a whole does not tell us how and why this agent
is making specific decisions. And, if we need and want to understand how
agents decide to understand interactions and transactions, then we need to
devise some radically new kind of microeconomics. Guerrien's
nihilistic stand here does not help us to move forward. Neoclassical microeconomics has to be taught (in an
abbreviated form of course) to allow students to move forward, but also to
equip them to understand the language the autistic economist uses. After all,
you could never understand history of the XIIth to XIVth Century without a good knowledge of the Catholic
dogma, which does not mean you have to believe in it, or even in God. ___________________________________ SUGGESTED
CITATION: For Guerrien… and beyond SUGGESTED
CITATION: Teaching
students of political science post-autistic economics Poul Thøis Madsen (Aalborg
University, Denmark)
Choice and use of text books It was very difficult to choose an appropriate textbook
for this target group. Currently, my preferred choice is ‘Economics’ by Mulhearn and Vane (Macmillan, 1999) because it is explicitly
targeted at non-economist students. Many economics textbooks, even very basic
ones, address, intentionally or unintentionally, students who are pursuing a
degree in economics. For our target group, these textbooks rely too heavily
on mathematical and graphical representations of economics and focus on the
current (or often even rather out-dated!) economic theoretical debate rather than the debate on actual economic problems. More importantly, in standard textbooks - intended or not
- the students are drawn into an autistic
world for the sake of being there and not much else. Somehow, teachers and
authors of textbooks seem to believe that students who stay within this
universe long enough will gradually learn how to analyse actual economic
problems and the related debates (which is the basic intention of our
teaching). Neither standard textbooks nor standard teaching really address
the acute and difficult problem of linking
the models presented to reality (defined as the actual economic
development, the actually applied economic policies and the real life debates
on economic issues). In essence, the occasional real life examples in
textbooks serve as mere illustrations of the often very abstract arguments
presented, thus, serving as some kind of entertainment without becoming an
integrated part of the argument. The partly implicit and partly explicit
working assumption in text books is that the more formal models presented to
the students, the more they will - somehow - be able to understand of the working
of the real economy. This is doubtful - to say the least - for many reasons.
One important reason is that the assumptions in many models do not survive
the meeting with 'reality' as defined above. A preliminary conclusion to be drawn from our experience
is that we can help the students by organising our teaching more consciously
and directly around basic economic
causalities (such as: expansive fiscal policy, increased economic
activity, increased employment, increased imports). These causalities should
be discussed at length. What are the basic assumptions? What is kept ceteris
paribus and why? How certain are these causalities? What do different
economic theories tell us about these causalities? Do the causalities work in
any kind of society, for example, industrialised and developing? What are the assumptions concerning the
institutional setting? Etc. The next logical step is to introduce (economic) politics
and discuss what possibilities exist for them to manipulate or intervene in
economic causalities. This is another obvious occasion for introducing
different theoretical perceptions - in this case the limits and possibilities
of economic policy. What
would we like the students to learn? As a consequence of our reforms, we have also changed the
way we examine the students. Years
ago one extreme but common practice during examinations was to make the
students derive the simple Keynesian model right from scratch (and, provided
the students were very clever, they were asked to do the same exercise with
the ISLM-model). For most of our students this took
up most of their examination time. And
the weaker the student, the more he or she stumbled on their road to –
what? More often than not students would
not have time to discuss actual economic policy or the limits of the models
(usually teachers claimed that this was the ideal intention underlying this
type of examination). In recent years examinations have become much more
human (traditionalist economists would say ‘lax’), the examination being based on the papers
produced by the students. In these papers they apply and discuss the
economic causalities most likely to be of actual economic relevance. For example, in a recent semester the
students discussed the possible consequences of the economic policies of the new
Danish right wing government. This focus on real life economic causalities, at the
expense of time spent on formal models, creates uncertainty for the students and to a
lesser extent for the teachers. Despite the shift of emphasis, the models still
tend to be seen as ‘the state of the art’ to be taught by
teachers and learned by the students. Consequently, the students expect to be
examined on the formal models and they become a bit frustrated and surprised
when in the main they are asked to relate the learned causalities to real
life instances. It is also seen by many as easier and fairer to the
students to tell them that they will be examined on the formal models. In
this way economics becomes one of the few fields within social science at
university level in which we are able to state very precisely what is
required. Personally, I see this as a
weakness – not a strength. To quote Keynes: “It is better to be
vaguely right than exactly wrong”. Seen from my perspective, teaching
the students how to make ‘vaguely right’ analyses and conclusions
should be the basic goal of teaching economics. My view is that the teaching and learning of models should
take up at most 10% of our time. Our students, but also students in general,
should learn how to ‘think’ and in this case to ‘think
economics’. What does this involve? First of all this is much more
diffuse and more difficult than handling rather simplified formal models.
Basically, it means learning how to make realistic assumptions and to discuss
the possible causalities within the field defined or framed by these
assumptions. Moreover, the clever students should also be able to question
these basic assumptions. And of course they should learn to consider both the
implications of relaxing the assumptions and to discuss the degree of realism
of the different assumptions made. Hereby, economics becomes just like any
other social science and henceforth also looses its aura of infallibleness.
This is a very important and not at all hidden part of the agenda underlying
the reforms.
Thus turning the usual way of doing things upside down. But – and this is important – they should not be taught models for the sake of
models. They should be taught models for two reasons:
We have also asked them what they have learned. Here are three examples (my translations): 1. 'I have learned a lot. I can follow the economic
political debates.' 2. 'I feel better equipped to understand economics, as it
is in the real world' 3. 'I can read a newspaper article and relate it to an
economic causality. It feels good' This is what I understand by post-autistic economics! _______________________________________ Poul Thøis Madsen, Aalborg
University, e-mail: pmadsen@humsamf.auc.dk SUGGESTED
CITATION:
Helge Peukert (University of Erfurt,
Germany) Edward Fullbrook
(editor): Intersubjectivity in Economics: Agents and Structures.
Routledge: London and New York, 2002. 306 pp. It should be mentioned at the beginning of this article
that the initiative to review this excellent and inspiring book originated
with the reviewer (and not the editor of this journal). The book consists of 17 articles, mainly by French and
British, but also American and German authors. The authors adhere to
different schools of thought, but they all treat economic agents as intersubjective entities.
Taken as a whole, the volume offers a number of different kinds of
groundwork for a new theoretical approach to economics intended to capture
the social embeddedness of economic actions and the
complexity and interdependency of economic agents. In particular, the book investigates the
social, cultural and economic structures which these agents construct. Fullbrook’s chapter
tries to show that the concept of comparative exchange-value produces
paradoxes because it is circular. Frank Ackerman’s chapter also tries
to demonstrate flaws in the foundations of mainstream economics with respect
to consumer behavior and general equilibrium
theory. Instead of demonstrating the optimality of market processes, the
theoretical debates in the 1970s, especially the Sonnenschein-Mantel-Debreu
theorem, proved that almost any continuous pattern of price movements can
occur in a general equilibrium model. Ackerman shows that these skeptical results depend, to a large degree, on the less
specified and unrealistic assumptions of the traditional model of consumer behavior. “The assumption of asocial individualism
in neoclassical economics guarantees that the aggregation problem is
insurmountable” (p. 63). Ackerman then presents some ideas for an
alternative theory in the tradition of Veblen,
Galbraith, Duesenberry and others. Ralph W. Pfouts’ essay
also asks for a more complete ontology of the consumer, one that does not
ignore the role played by factors like envy and imitation in consumer
behaviour. John Davis´ article on
collective intentionality, on the other hand, operates on a more conceptual
and philosophical level. Referring mainly to Tuomela´s
work, he tries to show that shared intentions exist without any recourse to,
for example a Hegelian super-mind. Davis shows that these we-intentions are
reciprocally related in a way that re-enforces them. Geoffrey Hodgson´s profound and
well-argued contribution also deals with ontological questions, especially
with the relationship between methodological individualism and collectivism
and the agency-structure distinction, and how Critical Realists (Bhaskar) and Giddens (with the
duality of structures approach) deal with them. Hodgson points out that,
besides some similarities, some fundamental and often neglected differences
with respect to a stratified ontology and the existence and importance of
emergent and structural properties must be considered. “Bhaskar thus upheld the dualism of agency and structure
that Giddens conflated into his singular, but
Janus-faced, ´duality´” (p. 163). But Hodgson criticizes the way that Bhaskar leaves open the questions of how reasons and
states of mind are caused. Paul Lewis and Jochen Runde also argue from a critical realist perspective and
contrast it with Kate and Edward Fullbrook´s
phenomenological intersubjectivist approach as
developed in the fifth chapter of their Simone
de Beauvoir (1998): consciousness is a
transitive relation that requires objects for its existence and that is
strongly influenced by the observations of other people. Lewis and Runde argue that a strictly intersubjective
position with a strong emphasis on mimetic behavior
ignores objective societal structures and sets of hierarchical lines, vested
interests, etc. Ernst Fehr and Armin Falk demonstrate that laboratory experiments show
the existence of reciprocal fairness, i.e. the willingness to sacrifice
resources for rewarding fair and punishing unfair behavior.
Usually a significant proportion of actors do not behave like rational
egoists. This heartening result of a deviation from pure self-interest is
reinforced by S. Abu Turab Rizvi’s
chapter which, from its history of economic thought perspective, considers
Adam Smith´s concept of sympathy in his Theory of Moral Sentiments. Anne Mayhew, in an elegantly written contribution, argues
that all consumption is conspicuous and explores the consumer´s role as a part of a group that seeks to mark
outsiders. As Sahlins and Baudrillard
underlined, consumption is an exchange of meanings and a discourse that can
signal both solidarity and superiority (Veblen). Roger Mason traces the often ambiguous reflection of
status seeking-consumption in economics. He starts with Mandeville, continues
with the ambivalent Adam Smith, and then moves on to the severe criticism of
J. Rae of such consumption on moral and religious grounds. The approaches to consumption of Cournot, Marshall, Pigou, Veblen and Keynes, as well as the history of the relative
income hypothesis, Hirsch´s positional goods
problem and R. Frank´s heterodox approach, are also
reviewed and critiqued. Peter Wynarczyk offers a
critique of the Chicago approach (Becker, Stigler) to criminal participation:
law establishes a set of prices (penalties) which influence conduct. The
author criticizes their view of human beings as pleasure/pain calculators and
makes the case for the importance of intersubjective
factors in the determination of rates of crime. Dupuy
compares Hayek´s and Keynes´ concepts of imitation
as a basis for an intersubjectively inspired
original understanding of the market process in the tradition of the French
conventions school (A. Orléan). Without any
underlying necessity, self-reinforcing dynamics can be created when two
persons A and B imitate each other.
Due to a rumor, A believes that he knows
what B desires. “A now knows what he needs to desire ... his own action
brings the object O of B´s attention, and when B
manifests in turn his interest in O, A has proof that his initial hypothesis
was correct” (p. 140). What Hayek fails to see but Keynes emphasized,
is that imitation may create costly illusions which can considerably
destabilize economic systems. Frédéric Lebaron examines the revival of economic sociology in
France, especially the project of the recently deceased Piere
Bourdieu.
Still another exercise in French sensitivity to the originality of the
human mind, the embededdness of human action and the
intersubjective context is Thévenot´s
critique of one-dimensional rationality. Fortunately, his cité-approach is briefly highlighted in Thierry Levy´s
contribution, which applies the theory of conventions to the question of
product quality. For Thévenot, every social context
is framed. “Correct” framing is difficult because a fundamental
uncertainty about (1) the competence of the actors, (2) the set of relevant
objects and (3) the mode of their coordination may exist. For example, in the case of a blood donor:
the situation can be interpreted in market terms or as a civic action, the
donor seen as naïve or generous. Two contributions deal with (cognitive) network effects as
potentials for market failures. Shaun P. Hargreaves
Heap argues that people watch TV in part because it is a conversational
resource. The demand for a program depends on the number of other program
consumers. The key to success is to win an initial audience. This results in
a bias for the familiar and sensational, a tendency which could be controlled
by regulation. . Paul Ormerod shows that even slight deviations from market perfection can have implications which lead to results far removed from the standard case of perfect competition. Without the presumption of increasing returns (with constant returns and an undifferentiated product) a strong tendency for oligopolies or even a monopoly may exist when we assume that firms have different levels of cost from the beginning (e.g. due to different management efficiency). This result runs counter to the very common viewpoint that globalization, more advanced information technologies and the reduction of transactions costs lead to an increase in competition. The importance of Fullbrook´s
book in the context of the post-autistic economics movement lies in the fact
that it substantiates the criticism of the mainstream. At the same time it
offers some new vistas for an alternative research agenda. SUGGESTED
CITATION: Some recent articles on PAE from the international press“The
Storming of the Accountants” The New Statesman (UK) 21 January 2002 “Post-autisten' vallen economische heilige huisjes aan” De Morgen (Bruxelles) 2 March, 2002 “Distorted economic
relations: A new movement – the post-autistic economists – wants
to renew economics” ____________________________________________________________________________________________________ EDITOR: Edward Fullbrook _____________________________________________________________________________________________________ Subscribe a
colleague(s) to this journal by sending their email address to To
subscribe to this journal, send an email with the message
"subscribe" to To
unsubscribe to this journal, send an email with the message
"unsubscribe" to
|
|
|