post-autistic
economics review |
|||
issue 15
contents PAE
Review index
home page |
|||
Towards a Realistic Epistemology for Economics
© Copyright 2002 Claude Mouchot
If
there is one point on which all economists would agree, it is that they will
never agree. And of course these
disagreements have always existed.
There was a time when we attributed them to the “youthfulness” of our
discipline, but today we are forced to admit that economics will remain
eternally “youthful”. It therefore
seems critical that we abandon this “youth” fable, as well as stop aiming for
the unification of our discourse; a fable and an aim that arise from
comparing economics to physics. That a
century after Walras some of us still hold to the
same epistemological position as he is, at the very least, surprising. I wish to propose here a realistic epistemology for the “science of
economics” that hopefully will enable us to explain our perpetual
disagreements and thus the reasons why economics is pluralist. In order to avoid the temptation to state the argument in terms of
physics, let us begin by considering in
the context of economics the following key sentence from Thomas Kuhn. Normal science .
. . is predicated on the assumption that the scientific community knows what
the world is like. (1970, p. 5) One needs only to carefully re-read this sentence to realize that it
will never be applicable to the world of economics nor to the social world in
general. Economists will never agree
on what the economic world is like, and partly because of what such an
agreement would signify. It would mean
that the ideological oppositions that have always run through the conceptions
of man and society, the great visions of the world -- individualism / holism,
liberalism / socialism, etc. -- would have disappeared. Now each of us is aware that repression of
these oppositions is possible only by totalitarian means, and, moreover, the
worst of their kind; a totalitarianism that, with no form of explicit
violence, would prohibit even the very thought of the term ‘opposite’, given
that the very notion of opposition would be nonexistent! Therefore, since these oppositions are a part of society, it follows that economics will never be a “normal science” in T. S Kuhn’s sense of the words. The unification of economic theories will never be achieved, at least not in a democratic society. Hence it is necessary to abandon all reference to physics and to make a new effort to work out the epistemological status of our discipline.
Let
us begin by considering two “classical” definitions of economics. 1.
Economics is the
study of humanity in the ordinary affairs of everyday life. (A. Marshall) Economics is the science that
studies human behaviour in relation to ends and scarce resources having
alternative uses. (L. Robbins) It is clear that both definitions define not
just economics but also the entire social setting. The first definition includes, friendship,
fatigue, pain, power, prestige, etc. and for many people even war. The second definition is no less general as
it pertains to all finalized action, ( Godelier pg.
19 – 20), and, moreover, is at the very foundation of the totalitarianism
mentioned above. But if on the other had one tries to narrow these definitions by in
Marshall’s substituting “economic” for “ordinary” and in Robbin’s
substituting “economic ends” for “ends”, then the definitions dissolve in
obvious circularity. The impossibility of separating the economic from the social, and the
circularity of the definitions, ( economics is economics) which result when
this impossibility is ignored, illustrate the unfeasibility of defining
economics. This fact can be summed up by one word: economics is a Totalité. Defining
an object, involves distinguishing it from other aspects of reality, and one
cannot distinguish an aspect of reality, if not from within the whole of
which it is a part. The whole, on other hand, cannot be distinguished except
to say that is the whole! Let us
insist on the lack of a definition for the word ‘whole’. We have said that it sums up the problems
posed by the proposed definitions for economics, but it does not resolves
them. It only illustrates the
impossibility of definition in this case. Here we
have more or less reached a cul-de-sac: economics is economics, and not much
can be added to that. But of course it
does not end here, as the existence of numerous economic theories proves. Constructing Scientific Domains“a science sets out to adequately delimit
the problems likely to define a field of research and on which a consensus can
be reached……” (Piaget 1970, p 41) This simple sentence supports our proposition that “economics is not a
science” and explains it further: given that economics remains undefined, it
cannot as a whole be considered and accepted as a science. How then, should we go about effectively
delimiting these problems so as to be able to constitute a domain that can be
studied scientifically? My answer
takes the form of identifying a necessary and sufficient condition: In order to
develop a scientific discourse in economics, it is necessary and sufficient
to privilege certain aspects of this Totalité,
to distinguish the aspects that we wish to study, in other words, to define
the object of study. This
condition is sufficient. For example,
if I
define my object as the study of how an individual allocates his income among
different expenditure alternatives, I end up with the marginalist’s
consumer equilibrium theory. Or if I
define it as the study of the conditions under which the division of income
between wages and profits is made in a capitalist economy, I end up with a
production cost theory, either neo-Ricardien or
Marxist, depending on what further hypothesis are made. This condition is also necessary.
It follows from the demonstrated nature of Totalité.
Economics is economics, and nothing more can
be said about it without specifying the discourse, that is, without
prioritising certain aspects of this whole.
All positive economic discourse is simply the expression of a
certain point of view on economic reality, a point of view that consists of
defining an object within a whole and constructing for this object a
scientific theory. All the major approaches to economics involve the construction of a
scientific object focused on a particular aspect of the whole. Therefore,
classical, neoclassical, Marxist, and Keynesian theories, are sciences
highlighting certain aspects of economic reality, while equally neglecting
others. We may say that each of these sciences “cuts out” its object within
the whole of the social and economic reality. This can be represented
diagrammatically as follows: Classical Economics
Keynesian Economics Economics as a Whole
Neoclassical
Economics Marxist Economics Each theory neglects certain aspects of reality:
You will have noticed that in the preceding diagram, all the theories
intersect at the same point, this being the economic situation under
consideration. Furthermore, it is my
contention that these theories have one characteristic in common: although
they privilege different logics, each describes an aspect of every economic
situation. For example, all the
theories have elements for explaining the current unemployment condition in
France. Is it not E. Malinvaud who thinks this unemployment is partly
classical and partly Keynesian? To accept this is also to accept that the logic of a theory ends where
that of another begins. Consequently,
if we prioritise one logic over another and insist on pushing it to its
limits, we end up with absurdities, in theory as well as in practice. For examples:
Thus, each theory illuminates only one aspect of reality, and each
theory should allow a place for other theories to succeed which will
illuminate other aspects of reality.
The challenge then becomes the harmonisation of these numerous
theories. Finding a common structure for these discoursesThe impossibility of a logical harmonizationTalking about the logical harmonization of two or more theories, means
synthesizing them into one main theory that encompasses them all. Within this
main theory, the constituent theories would be considered as special cases,
arising for instance, within certain specified parameters. However, such a
harmonization is not possible. This impossibility has been historically proven: the multiplicity of economic
theories is itself a form of concrete proof.
If their logical harmonisation were possible, we would at least expect
that some of the theories would have been unified. This impossibility is also
inscribed within the very idea that we are proposing, i.e., that of economics
being a Whole within which each theory constructs its very own scientific
object. The results obtained will no doubt depend on the constructed object,
and there is no reason whatsoever why they should hold true for the objects of
other theories. The possibility of having contradictory results is, indeed, very high.
A good example is that of excess supply in the market. Before the Keynesian
period, economists claimed that lowering prices was all it took to attain
market equilibrium, be it the market of a particular good or the global
market. But although true in the former case (micro), it sometimes proved
false in the latter case (macro), even if each producer behaved “rationally”
by lowering the price. This is an example of how sometimes decisions taken by
a group of rational individuals can lead to global irrationality. Diverging scientific objects, disjointed theories, partial discourses,
disharmonious and at times contradictory logic -- despite all these, we still
have to continue. And so to explain and understand the economic reality as
well as act on it, it is necessary for us to harmonize the different
discourses in question. Given that logical harmonization is impossible, we
need to find other means of harmonizing these theories. A reasonable
harmonisation Given that we already have access to an abundant literature on the current economic reality, as well as the desire to act on it, how then can we harmonize the numerous different theories in the absence of all other forms of unification? All economic policy seeks to modify reality and, in principle, to
modify it in a precise direction with a view to realizing the particular
values -- solidarity, justice, equality, etc. -- that each individual regards
as “good reasons” for acting. Of
course it goes without saying that wanting something and the ability to have
it are two different things. Therefore, we still need to find mechanisms that
will enable us to create a “better” reality (with respect to the values we
hold); hence the necessity of a coherent analysis of the situation to be modified. It is precisely at this
point that the multiplicity of theories poses a problem: faced with different
explanations, it is evident that one explanation and only one has to be
chosen over the rest. If not, the actions taken may prove totally
ineffective, like accelerating and breaking simultaneously. So what should be
the criteria for this choice? Let’s review what was said
earlier. In principle what we are
saying is that whatever the concrete economic problem under consideration
(unemployment for instance), it can be explained within a number of different
logical structures, belonging to different theories. Consequently, the choice of criteria although
easy in the abstract may be difficult to implement in reality. The politician considers and attempts to
understand today’s dominate logic as it pertains to the real world situation
under consideration, so as to decide according to that logic the measures to
be undertaken. But the currently
dominate theory may not fit the current situation. For example, the current talk in favour of supply-side
oriented policies aimed at increasing investment makes no sense today in
France where both personal saving and the self-financing of business enterprises
are very high. Good reasons, careful consideration, decision making, choice of policy, temporary conclusions (because tomorrow, today’s conclusions will be revised as the dominate logic will not be the same); this set of elements defines what ‘reason’ means, way beyond and above simple rationality, and takes into full account individual freedom which, though limited, is part of the reality that enables man to confront reality. I have tried to clarify the reasons as to why economists perpetually differ in opinion. I have noted that each economist chooses the theory that supports the values that (s)he holds. It therefore follows that these differences of opinion among economists are only the reflections of the underlying political dispute. Our discipline, being far removed from the scientific status of the natural sciences and whose limits have been revealed, ought to be re-named “Political Economics”. References Hahn, Frank (1972), The Shares of
Wages in National Income : an Inquiry into the Theory of Distribution,
London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Kuhn, Thomas (1970), The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press. Mouchot,
Claude (1996), Méthodologie économique,
Paris, Hachette. Piaget, J. (1970), Épistémologie des sciences de l’homme,
Paris, Gallimard. ____________________________ SUGGESTED CITATION: Claude Mouchot, “Towards a Realistic Epistemology for
Economics”, post-autistic economics
review, issue no. 15, September 4, 2002, article 5, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue15/Mouchot15.htm |