post-autistic economics review
Issue no. 30, 21 March 2005
article 4

 

 

      issue 30 contents                            PAE Review index                               home page

 

 

 

Finding a Critical Pragmatism in Reorienting Economics

 

Bruce R. McFarling   (University of Newcastle, Australia)

© Copyright 2005 Bruce R. McFarling

 

 

There is an "ology" that pervades the essay in which Tony Lawson (2003) launches Reorienting Economics.  The preface would lead us to believe it should be ontology.  However, while ontology receives starring credit, it is epistemology that plays the starring role.

 

This first essay is structured into four theses.  In his first thesis (2003: 3-8), the focus is on the mode of explanation of modern economics.  This is argued to be deductivism, defined as explanation in terms of event regularities.  Lawson refers to systems exhibiting event regularities as "closed", which can make his work difficult to read for someone with a General Systems background.  For someone more accustomed to thermodynamic or causal closure, it is helpful to mentally translate "closed" as "event-regular" everywhere Lawson uses the term.  The argument proceeds that this mode of explanation in terms of event-regular systems leads to the peculiar types of mathematical formalisms with which we are all familiar.

 

In his second thesis, Lawson points out the ill-health of the "mainstream project" (2003: 8).  This consists in large part of remarks taken from mainstream economists that reflect upon this poor state of health.  It is conceded that they rarely lay the blame on the peculiar type of mathematical formalism that forms the touchstone of mainstream economics.  However, with respect to "ology" sighting, the essential point is Lawson's conclusion:

" ... there is quite widespread agreement that the modern discipline is not in too healthy a condition, and that whatever explains the fact that the formalistic mainstream project has risen to such dominance ..., it has little to do with this project's record so far in explaining the social world in which we live. (2003: 11)"

 

In the first two theses, Lawson has been laying the foundation for the critique presented as the third thesis.  Yet the foundation for his ontological turn in economics is epistemological.  He argues that it is not the content of the theory in the mainstream content that is stable over time, but rather its mode of explanation.  To justify an interest in the ontology to follow, he presents a picture of the mainstream project in ill health.  Yet the symptom of ill health is that it is not succeeding in explaining.

 

In the third thesis  Lawson enquires what ontology is implied by event-regular systems, and how closely does this match the ontology of social systems?  Lawson argues (2003: 13-15) that there is an extremely strong bias (although not an ironclad necessity) toward an atomistic view of such systems, where the individual agents are simple and react in at least stochastically deterministic ways in response to given conditions.  There is also argued (2003: 15-16) to be a strong bias toward viewing systems as isolated systems.  This argument is easily followed, since a system composed of nothing but deterministic, atomistic agents will not be homeostatic, so that the state of such a system becomes indeterminate if the system is exposed to indeterminate external influences.

 

Lawson (2003: 16-17) then claims a variety of characteristics of social reality.  For example, positions in social reality are internally related, the social realm is structured, and it contains value and meaning.  As none of the features in this list can be exhibited by a purely atomistic and isolated system, it is concluded that much of what economics needs to be explained is incompatible with its implicit ontology.

 

Lawson (2003: 18-20) argues that this incompatibility is responsible for the constant appearance of the central fictions of mainstream economics.  These central fictions are a familiar fixture.  They bear a surface similarity to the isolating fictions of scientific theory.  For example, a natural scientist will adopt the fiction of a weight dropping through a vacuum to eliminate the real additional influence of wind resistance.  However, because deductivism is constructing a theory in a fictitious world that is supposed to correspond to events in the real world, it seems that its fictions cannot be restricted to the absence of forces that are in fact likely to be present.  They must also include the presence of fictitious forces to take the place of real world influences that cannot be expressed in an atomistic and isolated system.

 

While ontology is brought on stage here, it is certainly not appearing solo.  The essence of the argument here is that the mainstream mode of explanation is not capable of explaining what Lawson wishes to explain.  Certainly, it may be granted that Lawson's wish to explain particular aspects of reality is an ontological concern.  However, the capabilities of a mode of explanation is an epistemological concern, and that is certainly the crux of the argument.  Without the limited capabilities of the mainstream mode of explanation, the critique falls over.  With the limited capabilities there is something of substance to the critique, even if one differs with Lawson's ontology.

 

The final thesis is the conclusion of the critique.  Adherence to a mode of explanation in terms of event-regular systems is the reason for the lack of health, and is indeed the constraint preventing mainstream economics from being scientific.  It is argued that even where science deliberately constructs event-regular systems in an experimental setting, it does so to form a cause and effect theory applicable to non-event-regular systems.  (Lawson 2003: 22-26) The argument may be seen as claiming that the mainstream mode of explanation is not a scientific mode of explanation.  Here, too, the argument seems as much epistemological as ontological.

 

It should be stressed that this argument has substantial merit.  Constructing a theory in an abstract event-regular system is not, in fact, the same thing as constructing an experiment – an artificial event-regular system in the real world.  In the former case, the event-regular system has no necessary connection with a real world non-event-regular system.  In the latter case, the fact that it is constructed in the real world of real components provides the connection with the same components interacting in a non-event-regular system.

 

While the starring role of epistemology is the strength of the argument, the anonymity of the star is a weakness.  Possessing a mode of explanation that implies an inadequate ontology is not necessarily a critical flaw.  As long as the explanatory process allows the worst mismatches to be replaced by less severe mismatches, one can hope that the mode of explanation may evolve toward one that implies an adequate ontology.

 

The central question, therefore, has not changed in a century, because while theoretical stances within the mainstream project have proliferated and shifted ground, essential aspects of its mode of explanation have not changed in a century.  That question is, why do mainstream economists not engage in evolutionary science? (Veblen, 1898).  Of particular interest for the past 60 years is how a determined effort to subject theories to statistical analysis have left the mainstream project every bit as stalled as it was a century ago.

 

Lanis and McFarling (2004) point in the direction of one flaw.  We construct a highly artificial, highly regular scenario in the context of explaining the degree of disclosure of accountants in the context of different national accounting and economic institutions.  However, the scenario we have constructed is non-functional.  That is, legal, professional and commercial institutions will establish norms for what must be disclosed to provide an adequate report, what may be reported, and what ought to be reported in exceptional circumstances, and what ought not to be reported.

 

Any mathematical relation connects elements from its domain to elements from its range.  In our artificial scenario, we relate a score on a synthetic index of social attitudes to the degree of disclosure within the accounting institutions of a nation.  A functional relation connects either one or many elements from the domain to one element in the range.  Any relation that connects either one or many elements from the domain to multiple elements in the domain is therefore non-functional.  Regression analysis, where it is used correctly, overcomes the problem of relating to multiple scattered observations by constructing the function in terms of a probability distribution, so that the scattered observations are interpreted as different samples drawn from the same distribution.

 

However, the regularity in our scenario is on the bounds on reporting. Even if one viewed this range of discretion as a probability distribution, each shift in the bounds would result in a new probability distribution. The degree of discretion, which will vary from one institutional context to another, implies that the regularity is not functional – it is one collection of institutional norms to many possible degrees of disclosure.  Therefore, any effort to fit the best function will necessarily fail.  It appears that functional regularity is equivalent to Lawson's event-regularity.  We point out several statistical techniques that may be used with better effect – techniques which will only be picked up outside the mainstream project, if Lawson's argument regarding the event-regular epistemology of the mainstream mode of explanation is correct.

 

In any event, here is part of the answer to the puzzle of why sixty years of determined empirical testing has left the mainstream project stalled.  If your tool for finding and correcting mismatches with the real world fits functions to data, you will be left blind when the problem involves a regular relationship that is not a function.

 

A more specific epistemological query than the mode of explanation is the unit of analysis.  Any analytical explanation will involve one or more units of analysis, so that the phenomena to be explained are explained in terms of the unit of analysis.  In McFarling (2004), I find that the unit of analysis in a particular corner of the mainstream project to be selection from alternatives, followed by performance.  It may be noted in passing that this is essentially the same neoclassical unit of analysis that is ably dissected and subjected to acid critique by Veblen (1898) as part of an increasingly obsolete natural law approach, which he contrasts with a modern, evolutionary approach.  However, this unit of analysis was originally unearthed in the work of Posner (1995).  Thus, even if much of the theory of the mainstream project is in a state of flux, this unit of analysis clearly exhibits greater longevity.

 

I then pose the question whether it is possible to arrive at a theory of culture with such a unit of analysis, and argue it is not.  If culture acts in part as a restraint on action, then situating culture in the selection will erode those restraints.  And if culture is simply embedded in the constraints on decisions, then culture is a deus ex machina, affecting the outcome but not explained by the unit of analysis.  Culture cannot be analysed with selection followed by performance as the unit of analysis – it can at best be taken as a given.

 

What is the point of identifying the unit of analysis?  Being informed that the mainstream project is deductivist, based on presumed event-regularities, may make it easier to identify a mainstream economist.  However, it does not go very far in explaining how the mainstream economist is reproduced.  The unit of analysis, on the other hand, goes a long way toward explaining the reproductive process.  The first thing a nascent researcher needs to learn is what type of questions to ask.  And the unit of analysis provides a trio of questions that can be asked about individuals in a wide variety of settings.  What selections are faced by this individual?  Which one is likely to be selected?  And what performance is likely to follow that selection?

 

The attraction of this unit of analysis is that there are always more puzzles to solve.  If you try to provide a complete theory of the economy with a unit of analysis that is blind to important aspects of the economy, each new trial solution will prove to be a misfit when it encounters the affects of one or more excluded aspect.  And if the reaction to a misfit is to start over with the same trio of questions, there will always be a permutation of available selections and likelihood of occurrence that has not been tried before.

 

Given this unit of analysis, a question that arises is whether ontology can be used to reorient mainstream economics.  Supposed this is your unit of analysis in developing new explanations, and suppose econometrics is your tool for finding out what the problem is with your explanations.  How will you react when being told that there are certain features of the social world that do not fit the ontology implicit in your method?  You will interpret these features in terms of your unit of analysis.

 

Indeed, you may devise econometric tests to determine whether the features as you have interpreted them are present in the data you have available.  If you get statistically significant results, you may even publish the outcome in a respectable mainstream journal.  Yet you are not likely to have made a step toward evolutionary science.  When interpreting the features with your unit of analysis, you will omit what is incompatible with your unit of analysis.

 

Indeed, in McFarling (2004), I find hope in New Institutional analysis.  This comes from the argument that the New Institutional unit of analysis is the transaction, followed by performance.  Yet there is not necessarily an ontological advance here.  Indeed, it may be that New Institutional analysis maintains its credibility within the mainstream project in part by adhering to the same flawed ontology as follows from the neoclassical unit of analysis (though see David Dequech 2002).  However, by placing the selection in the context of a transaction between two individuals, the unit of analysis admits questions regarding relationships between individuals that the neoclassical unit of analysis does not admit.  The conclusion is not that New Institutional economics is an evolutionary science, but rather that it is not prevented from being an evolutionary science by its unit of analysis.

 

The dangerous face of epistemology is the invitation to focus on the ways that we understand the ways that we understand things.  And it is when I consider the mode of explanation in this essay that I come upon a concern.  Event-regular systems are classified as closed systems.  Everything else are classified as open systems.

 

One thing this blinds us to is any other kind of regularity.  Suppose that an individual has a regular response to a cluster of events, where a response consists of one of a range of actions that are meaningful in that context.  Response-regular systems are not necessarily event-regular, but it is a form of regularity.  Suppose that an individual has a response that is within regular bounds, with clear discretion within those bounds.  Boundary-regular systems are not necessarily event-regular, but it is a form of regularity.  Suppose that a system is homeostatic, so that the response to an event is contingent on the discrepancy between the current internal state of the system and the target internal state.  A homeostatic system would only approach event regularity in a perfectly homogenous environment where events are sufficiently infrequent so that the state prior to the event closely approximates the target state.  Yet not only is homeostasis a form of regularity, but a collection of homeostatic systems can create regularity in a wider system.

 

In other words, in this system of classification, we are to label event-regular systems as closed and all other systems as open, whether or not they exhibit one or several other forms of regularity.  If you need event-regular systems to be a reputable mainstream economist, this may suffice to tell us whether a person is pursuing that status or rejecting it in favour of status with some other peer group.  However, suppose we accept Lawson's argument that adequate economic theory will normally have to be compatible with an "open" system.  We have a simple dichotomy here, and the positive category is the one to be avoided.  Reorientation is required because the pursuit of theories of closed systems is and will continue to be fruitless in generating effective explanations.  Yet saying that the reorientation will take open systems as the object of theory is to say that it will take "not-event-regular" systems as the ultimate object of theory. It is, in short, simply a restatement of the "though shalt not" dictum, except that this time the "not" has been located inside the term "open".

 

Thus in trying for a positive statement, Lawson must elaborate on what kind of open system he means.  That elaboration appears to be whatever kind of open system is compatible with social ontology and his realist transformational model of social activity.  And it is here that the argument appears to become controversial.  As Vromen (2004) points out, there is a substantial inconsistency between the qualifications with which Lawson wraps this model, and the ultimate authority that Lawson grants it as a final arbiter between properly and improperly oriented economic theory.

 

This is the crux of the question of whether ontology or epistemology should have the starring role in this play.  If we have the "right" ontology, how did we discover that it is the right ontology?  And if we have a way of discovering the right ontology, which is more fruitful to convey: the method of discovery; or the ontology itself as received wisdom?

 

Of course, this is a counterfactual.  As strongly suggested by the qualifications that Lawson places on his ontology – that it is "… practically conditioned, historical and fallible" (Lawson 2003, 61) – it would appear that at most we can say that our ontology seems to be the best we can do at the moment.  As Vromen appears to be arguing, this is a weak basis for launching a revolution.

 

The implicit recognition of this is built into the structure of Lawson's first essay.  Accepting that the mainstream project is generating a flurry of explanations without succeeding in explaining anything is supposed to generate interest in considering the suitability of the underlying ontology.  Epistemology is providing the wedge intended to create an opening.  Lawson's particular social ontology is then supposed to enter the gap that is created.

 

Yet how are we to discriminate between different explanations, once we have reoriented ourselves to open systems?  I skip past the ontology of the second essay and the realism of the third to the essay on explanations in social science.  Lawson describes a method of forming hypotheses in terms of relative contrasts that are to be expected if a hypothesis is correct.  He then argues that "The hypothesis that performs best in terms of empirical adequacy in this sense over the widest range of relevant conditions can, with reason, be accepted as better grounded. (2003: 97)"

 

What we have here, of course, is a pragmatic criterion for judging the epistemological fitness of a mode of explanation and unit of analysis – or units of analysis, since the criterion accepts successful eclecticism as readily as successful and rigorous modes of explanation.  Note that this is a basis for a pluralism that extends beyond those approaches that we agree with.  We can accept that a mode of explanation is progressing under this criterion even if we think its ontology is flawed and that its conclusions are fallacious.  Indeed, one can hope that if it continues to pursue a broader range of successful explanation, it will either eliminate the source of the fallacies, or it will develop an explanation that shows why we have misunderstood the question all along.

 

This, then, is Lawson's critical pragmatism.  I naturally refrain from systematising it, since in that case it would be my pragmatism rather than his.  Its core is the epistemology that Lawson works out as a side-effect of bridging the gap between his critical realism and a potentially scientific practice of economics.  I conjecture that it is narrower in scope than the virtual blank slate offered by the concept of the open system, but broader in scope than the social ontology constructed in terms of his realist transformational model of social activity.

 

 

References

 

Dequech, David. (2002). "The demarcation between the "old" and the "new" institutional economics: Recent Complications". Journal of Economic Issues; June 2002, vol. 36, pp. 565-572.

Lanis, Roman and Bruce R. McFarling. (2004) " Healthy Economics Healing Autistic Accounting Theory: Visiting a Neglected Area of Institutional Economics." Journal of Economic Issues.  Vol. 38 (1).  March 2004.  pp. 59-83.

Lawson, Tony. (2003). Reorienting Economics. Title in Economics as Social Theory, Tony Lawson, ed. London: Routledge. 383pp.

McFarling, Bruce R. (2004) "The Clarence Ayres Memorial Lecture: An Institutionalist Reconstruction of Culture." Journal of Economic Issues. Vol. 38 (2), June 2004. pp. 339-52.

Posner, Richard A. (1995) "The New Institutional Economics Meets Law and Economics." Overcoming Law. Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Mass. pp. 426-443.

Veblen, Thorsten. (1898) "Why is Economics Not an Evolutionary Science" The Quarterly Journal of Economics. Vol. 12 (4), July 1898. pp. 373-397.

Vromen, Jack. (2004) “Conjectural Revisionary Ontology ”, post-autistic economics review, No. 29, 6 December 2004. article 4, http://www.btinternet.com/~pae_news/review/issue29.htm


___________________________
SUGGESTED CITATION:
Bruce R. McFarling,
“Finding a Critical Pragmatism in Reorienting Economics ”,  post-autistic economics review, issue no. 30, 21 March 2005, article 4, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue30/McFarling30.htm