post-autistic economics review
Issue no. 29, 6 December 2004
article 2

 

 

      issue 29 contents                            PAE Review index                               home page

 

 

 

 

The Political Economy of Destructive Power

 

Mehrdad Vahabi   (Université Paris 8, France)

© Copyright 2004 Mehrdad Vahabi

 

 

1. Destructive power: a new field of study


From its inception, Political Economy has been interested in analysing the value that agents, individually or collectively, can produce or exchange at national or international levels. According to Say, Political Economy has to be “confined to the science which treats of wealth” andunfolds the manner in which wealth is produced, distributed, and consumed” (Jean-Baptiste Say, [1821] 1964, p. xv). The main object of Political Economy is thus the productive power of human beings. But what about their destructive power? This latter question is not less important than the traditional central question of  Political Economy, since it is easier to destroy than to create. In fact, we are able to destroy a hundred or even thousand times more than what we can create.


The creative power of an ordinary healthy high-school graduate may amount to no more than four or five thousand dollars of value per year. This creative or positive economic power refers to the graduate’s capacity to produce or to exchange.  But that is not the only economic power that he possesses.  As an extortionist, for example, he can destroy a hundred times more.  Futhermore, extortion can be used by a criminal, a brigand, or a revolutionary. Whatever the extortionist’s motive, it is destructive power, the power to destroy use values or exchange values, that he uses. Is the question how much can an agent destroy irrelevant to Political Economy? Neoclassical economists say that it is.

 

Neoclassical economics rejected social disequilibrium and conflict, and assumed a sustainable harmony among individual agents through a market economy. Consequently, revolutions or radical conflicts undermining the social system are considered to be “unnatural” or irrational, and thus treated as actions resulting from passions and emotions and not from reason. Since by definition Neoclassical economics was the study of “rational behaviour”, the study of this type of irrational behaviour was, as Pareto urged, delegated to sociology, politics, psychology and history. Of course, Pareto ([1902] 1966) acknowledges that “The efforts of men are utilized in two different ways: they are directed to the production or transformation of economic goods, or else to the appropriation of goods produced by others”. However, since the appropriative activity does not come within the scope of free choice, it can not under the Neoclassical view concern the economist.

 

It is true that elementary textbooks frequently introduce the production possibilities frontier between “guns” and “butter” (as Samuelson’s favourite example describes the optimal allocation of resources in his Economics, 1948) to illustrate the nature of the economic problem and the concept of opportunity cost. It is noteworthy, however, that they never consider the question of how “guns” might be used in a destructive manner to appropriate resources from neighbouring peoples or states, and thus push out the production possibilities frontiers of the society.

 

I propose an alternative approach to Political Economy, one that considers both the creative and the destructive power of human beings.  This requires that a new field of study, namely destructive power, be explored by economists. This field consists not of fragmented and specialized studies regarding the military sector, criminal activities or the economics of warfare. Instead it embraces the destructive power of human beings in all its diverse forms. Federating existing fragmented studies will not achieve a general comprehension of destructive power, because these studies are based on standard and inappropriate economic assumptions and methods, such as maximizing and rationality behaviour, and individual cost/benefit analysis.  In this paper I am going to explain what I mean, in an economic context, by destructive power.

 

 

2. Definition of destructive power

 

To understand destructive power, we must distinguish between destruction as an integral part of “creation” (or what Hegel calls “specific, limited or definite negation”) and destruction as the antithesis of creation (or what Hegel calls “abstract negation”, [1807]1977, pp. 359-60, 567-68).

 

 

2.1 Destruction as an integral part of creation

 

In a sense, destruction can be considered as the very act of creation, since all production involves what might be called “destructive transformation”, like wheat being ground into flour, or flour baked into bread (Boulding, 1989, p. 239). To produce a chair, we need to use, consume, and thus destroy wood, and the destruction of wood in a particular way leads to the construction of the chair. Final consumption can also be viewed as a form of destruction. Destroying a product through consumption is the counter part of creating utility. In this sense, destruction is part of creation.

 

In a similar way, innovative activity can be considered as creative destruction, as Schumpeter referred to the process of capitalist development (Schumpeter, 1951, chapter vii). This kind of destruction is the direct outcome of innovation, namely the destruction of old products, past processes of manufacturing and archaic forms of organisation through the introduction of new products, ways of producing, and organisational methods.

 

The process of learning is also a kind of self-destruction, namely the reshaping of our knowledge framework, the rearrangement or reconstruction of our data and mental representations, and through which biases can be removed or replaced by new ones. Science can be defined as a form of destruction, or a process of permanent destruction of certain ideas, concepts, or paradigms. The negation of past knowledge is mental destruction, which like material destruction, may give birth to the construction of something new, in this case new knowledge.

 

The accumulation of capital involves concentration and centralisation of different forms of capital (such as industrial, financial, or commercial capital) which results in the elimination of small property owners. Property rights are not limited to holding things for oneself, since through capitalist development, they result in withholding things from others (Commons, [1924] 1995, pp. 53-54). Thus this process of capital accumulation generates bankruptcy, i.e. the destruction of certain firms and the creation of new firms, job destruction and job creation, as well as mergers and acquisitions in financial markets with their direct consequences in terms of value creation and value destruction. Competition as a natural selection mechanism of capitalism brings into play forces necessary to weed out elements which can hinder capitalist development. Budget, monetary and financial constraints provide economic sanctions through which competition exerts its full power as a selection mechanism. In all these cases, destruction is an integral part of the creative process. Overconsumption and overproduction are part and parcel of economic crisis. Karl Marx clearly speaks of the “destruction of capital” through crises (Marx, Part II, [1861-3]1978, pp. 495-96) and distinguishes two different meanings of capital destruction during crises, namely destruction of real capital (use-value and exchange value) and destruction of capital defined as depreciation of exchange values. Destruction of capital through crises constitutes a necessary moment of the capitalist reproduction process. In this respect, destruction of values is an integral part of value-creation. Nonetheless, the destructive power of crises is a “spontaneous” or an “unintended” destruction which does not result from strategic decisions of individuals or social groups.

 

 

2.2 Destruction as the antithesis of creation

 

To differentiate destruction from creation, we have to focus on abstract destruction, for which destruction is not just a moment of the creative process, but constitutes a moment in itself: it means destruction for the sake of destruction. This is what Boulding refers to as “the dark side of destructive power”, which goes back a long way, as shown in the story of Cain and Abel (1989, p. 22). This brings us once again to threat power which is different from creative power. The remainder of this paper will focus on this particular sense of destruction and destructive power rather than on destruction as an integral part of creation.

 

Strictly speaking, destructive power is threat power that may lead to the destruction of use or exchange values or even human beings and nature. This instrumental definition of destructive power is free of value judgments. I do not necessarily consider a destructive action to be a “bad” or Mephistophelian one. By the same token, a creative action is not necessarily a “good” action. In other words, my distinction between destruction and creation, as well as destructive and creative value is not based on an ethical criterion. It does not mean that the ethical or legitimising aspects of any recourse to destructive or creative power are denied, it simply implies that in this definition, the value has a purely instrumental character, and does not contain a judgmental value.

 

Moreover, destructive power should not be reduced to violence (revolution, civil war and war, terrorism, hostage taking or other criminal type of activities). It also includes non violent activities (strikes, demonstrations, or deliberate exclusion). Among different non-violent forms of destructive power, exclusion plays a key role. Exclusion is the supreme mechanism available to a dominant institution (academic, religious, political, economical or cultural) or a social group, caste, or nation, enabling it to exert its destructive power against opponents.

 

Destructive power is both physical and moral or spiritual. The earliest civilisations were allegedly based on priesthoods. Priests established social rules and threatened disobedient people with social exclusion or divine punishments. Non-believers were told they would be punished by preternatural powers and should expect to endure excruciating pains after their death by going to an awful place like hell, while believers were promised a blissful life in a beautiful place like paradise. Moral destructive power can be carried out through moral threat. However, there exist other forms of this power that cannot be reduced to moral threat. For instance, gossip is not a moral threat. But it can spread scandals against certain targeted people, put them down, exclude them from collective action or groups, and even morally lynch them. If in gossip, destroying one’s reputation is not necessarily based on the truth, in blackmailing, the non-revelation of the truth can be a source of power.

 

Lying and historical forgery are other forms of destructive power that can destroy individual or collective memory or identity. This sort of behaviour cannot be reduced to a situation of asymmetrical information. It may be deployed by a dominant group that tries to impose its “truth” by every means, including destroying facts, historical forgery and excluding non-believers. As Napoleon justly remarked: “What is history but a fable agreed upon”.

 

Finally, destructive power can be individual or social. When a child “cries” or “breaks things” and throws a tantrum to impose her/his desire on its parents, s/he is using her/his individual destructive power. But the power of a community to exclude or to sanction is its social destructive power. Destructive power has a strong integrative power. Its importance in social integration is such that the etymology of “society” gives credence to the idea that “society” was historically perceived as a military alliance. Let us examine the etymology of “society”. It derives from the Latin word societas. This elaborated socius, meaning a non-Roman ally, a group willing to follow Rome in War. Such a term is common in Indo-European languages, deriving from the root sekw, meaning “fellow”. It denotes an asymmetrical alliance, society as a loose confederation of stratified allies.” (Mann, 1986, p. 14). The recourse to destructive power is not only a symptom of crisis or disequilibrium, but a constant dimension of collective action.

 

 

3. Two different functions of destructive power

 

Destructive power has two different functions: appropriative and rule-producing. Although these functions are inextricable, I treat them separately for theoretical clarity. For example, the war of the Bush administration against Iraq is being waged to pirate Iraq’s petrol and to control its economy. In this sense, war as a form of destructive power has an appropriative function. But this colonialist war also has a rule-producing effect, since the United States tries to establish its sovereignty over Iraq, its hegemony in the Middle East, and perhaps to draw a new map for the whole region in co-operation with Israel. These two different functions are present in other forms of destructive power. A revolution is for changing rules, but it also has an appropriative aspect. In the case of strikes, the appropriative function is straightforward, since their targets are usually to increase salary, reduce working hours and so on. Nevertheless, strikes also decide on the way an enterprise should be run. For workers’ trade unions, striking is a very strong means that allows them to negotiate with employers concerning workers’ participation in the management. Even the right to strike is an important political question that involves the rule-producing function of destructive power. Criminal activity, as another form of destructive power, has both types of function. Its pirating or appropriative function is obvious, but it has a more enduring effect, namely a destabilising or rule-disturbing effect which implies disorder, anarchy, and insecurity.

 

 

3.1 Destructive power in its appropriative function

 

The difference between these two functions is crucial. Destructive power in its appropriative function is a means, whereas in its rule-producing function, it is an end in itself. In the former case, destructive power can be defined as an alternative means of reallocating resources. It can be dubbed “rent-seeking”, “predation”, “appropriative” and be integrated in a rational expectation or general equilibrium model of individual agents choosing between creative and destructive activities in accordance with their private costs and benefits. In a perfect world of fully informed agents with no randomness, and devoid of radical uncertainty, it can be shown that the appropriative function of destructive power may be realised with no real destruction or violence (See Grossman and Kim, 1995, 1996). All strands of the Neoclassical approach, such as rational conflict theory, general equilibrium models of violence, and socio-political instability models of new political economy lead to this result. Money neutrality in a general equilibrium model of creative activity is analogous to violence neutrality in a general equilibrium model of appropriative activity. In both cases, money and violence are considered to be the means to achieve a particular end. In Neoclassical theory, money neutrality is related to the role of money as a means of commodity circulation, or fiat money. By the same token, violence neutrality is related to the role of destructive power as a means of appropriation. In both cases, money and violence disappear in equilibrium. Agents are regarded as self-interested and calculating individuals endowed with ex ante rationality and maximising behaviour.

 

 

3.2 Destructive power in its rule-producing function

 

Destructive power in its rule-producing function resembles money as a store of wealth. Money in its function as a store of wealth is required for its own sake, for its liquidity and can be regarded as an end in itself. What determines the liquidity preference of people? “Our desire to hold Money as a store of wealth is a barometer of the degree of our distrust of our own calculations and conventions concerning the future […] The possession of actual money lulls our disquietude; and the premium which we require to make us part with money is the measure of the degree of our disquietude.” (Keynes, 1937, p. 216). Uncertainty about conventional judgements resulting from a multitude of agents’ anticipation about the state of the market in the future, and their distrust about their own calculations are the sources of liquidity preference. Money can serve as an insurance against uncertainty because of its social or universal value. Liquidity preference is thus decided not by individual agents but by conventional judgements, which are formed through a social process. In this process, the dominant opinion of the leading deciders in financial markets determines the social norm.

 

Destructive power in its rule-producing function is most likely required for its own sake, since it is the foundation of law or legal order. Destructive power as the last resort to maintain a desired order can overcome or mitigate our distrust about the possible violations of order by others. While the appropriative function of destructive power may be dealt with in an individualistic framework, the rule-producing function of this power can only be grasped in a social context. Keynes’s famous phrase “in the long run, we are all dead” reveals an important aspect of economic reasoning. Any individual is concerned first and foremost by economic interests during her/his personal lifetime. Individuals do not behave as species or dynasties with regard to their short-term economic interests. However, it is true that in war as well as revolutionary action “individualism is the first to disappear” (Fanon, 1968, p. 47). In such cases, one can observe a kind of group coherence which is more deeply felt and shared by large masses of people and shows a much stronger, but less enduring, attachment than all other varieties of private or civil friendship. Individual self-consciousness thus turns into a collective consciousness and the immortality of the species takes the centre stage of our experience. Nonetheless, it is not only in wars, revolutions, or other violent forms of action implying death that we are confronted with this sort of behaviour. In almost all protestations undermining the existing order, individuals become conscious of their role as part of a species or a dynasty. Broadly speaking, if economic reasoning leads to Keynes’s motto that “in the long run, we are all dead”, political reasoning results in the opposite motto “in the long run, we are all alive”. The time horizon of economic reasoning is different from that of political reasoning.

 

Destructive power in its appropriative function follows economic or private reasoning, whereas destructive power in its rule-producing function complies with political, social groups’ (classes) or public reasoning. This explains why the appropriative function of destructive power is consistent with an individualistic Neoclassical framework, while the rule-producing function of this power is in contradiction with such an approach.

 

 

Conclusion

 

Integrating both functions of destructive power into Political Economy is a new challenge for economists who think that economics should extend its traditional frontiers as a science of creative power of human beings. My objective is to bring together the question of sovereignty with that of property, which is more in tune with what Adam Smith (1776) considered to be the main concern of Political Economy: “The great object of the political economy of every country is to increase the riches and power of that country”. In doing so, I must emphasise that my intentions are free from economic imperialism for two reasons. First, I do not find the application of the present standard assumptions of economic analysis such as rationality and optimisation appropriate for my goal. Second, the integration of destructive power in economic analysis requires economics to come closer to other social sciences, such as philosophy, political science, psychology, sociology, and military science. Nevertheless, I think that in analysing the value of destructive power economists have something to say, since they have been dealing mainly with the issue of value over the last three centuries. As a student of social science, I have tried elsewhere (Vahabi, 2004), to take advantage of all social sciences that are relevant to my subject in order to contribute to the Political Economy of destructive power. This effort comes within the scope of an approach that regards Political Economy as a discourse both on the creative and destructive power of human beings.

 

 

Note

 

1. Contact address: Mehrdad.vahabi@wanadoo.fr. This article draws extensively on a book I have recently published: Mehrdad Vahabi, The Political Economy of Destructive Power (Edward Elgar, 2004).

 

 

References

Boulding, K.E., 1989, Three faces of power, Newbury Park, London, New Delhi, Sage Publications.

Commons, J.R., [1924] 1995, Legal Foundations of Capitalism, New Brunswick and London,

Transaction Publishers.

Fanon, F., 1968, The Wretched of the Earth, New York, Grove Press edition.

Grossman H., and Kim M., 1995, "Swords or Plowshares?  A Theory of the Security of Claims to

Property," Journal of Political Economy, vol. 103, pp. 1275-88.

Grossman, H., and Kim M., 1996, "Predation and Production", in Garfinkel M. and Skaperdas (eds.),

The Political Economy of Conflict and Appropriation, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Hegel, G.W.F., [1807] 1977, Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A.V. Miller with Analysis of the Text

and Forward by J.N. Findlay, F.B.A., F.A.A.A.S., Oxford, Clarendon Press.

Hirschman, A.O., 1970, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty, Cambridge Mass., Cambridge University Press.
Keynes, J.M., 1937, “The General Theory of Employment,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, February,

pp. 209-223.

Mann, M., 1986, The Sources of Social Power, vol. 1, A history of power from the beginning to A.D. 1760,

Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

Marx, K. [1861-63] 1978, Theories of Surplus-Value, 3 parts, Moscow, Progress Publishers.

Pareto, Vilfredo, [1902] 1966, Les Systèmes d’Economie Politique, in Finer S.E. (ed.), Vilfredo Pareto 

Sociological Writings, New York, Praeger.

Say, J.B., [1821] 1964, A Treatise on Political Economy or the Production, Distribution and Consumption

of Wealth, New York, Claxton, Remsen & Haffelfinger.

Schumpeter, J.A., 1951, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, London, George Allen and Unwin Ltd.

Smith, Adam, [1776]1961, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, London,

Methuen.

Vahabi, M., 2004, The Political Economy of Destructive Power, Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, USA,

Edward Elgar.


___________________________
SUGGESTED CITATION:
Mehrdad Vahabi
, “The Political Economy of Destructive Power”, post-autistic economics review, issue no. 29, 6 December 2004, article 2, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue29/Vahabi29.htm