post-autistic economics review
Issue no. 29, 6 December 2004
article 5

 

 

      issue 29 contents                            PAE Review index                               home page

 

 

 

Symposium on Reorienting Economics

 


Feminism, critical realism and economics:
a response to Van Staveren

 

Andrew Sayer   (Lancaster University, UK)

© Copyright 2004 Andrew Sayer

 

 

As someone who has benefited from reading both Irene van Staveren’s and Tony Lawson’s work I would like to respond to just two of the issues raised in van Staveren’s critique of Lawson in PAER, no. 28, for at various points it reproduces some common misunderstandings of realism (van Staveren, 1999; 2004; Lawson, 1997, 2003). These two issues are, first, the relations between essentialism, universalism and determinism, and, second, the nature of emotions. I believe that Lawson’s work already contains answers to van Staveren’s critique; in this response I basically wish to provide additional sources of support for Lawson’s position regarding these two sets of issues.



Essences, universalism and determinism

 

The term ‘essentialism’ has been used in many different ways, often involving slides between logically-independent meanings of the term, so that ‘anti-essentialism’ has a number of different targets (Sayer, 2000). However, I suggest that behind the debates on essentialism there are two primary fears: firstly a fear of epistemological dogmatism, involving claims to absolute truth or privileged access to the world; and secondly, a fear of an ontological assumption of determinism, according to which, what objects, including people, actually do, is completely determined by their nature. Both fears are justifiable, but the doctrines they concern are entailed neither by realism nor essentialism.

 

Regarding the first fear: claims about the world are, as Lawson insists, fallible. Questioning the authority of scientists implies – rightly – that they are fallible. But it is vital to appreciate what that presupposes – namely that there must be something existing independently of the claims about which they can be mistaken. Thus fallibilism presupposes at least a minimal realism – that the world is not simply a product of wishful thinking. If the world were merely whatever we socially constructed/construed it as, then that socially-constructed knowledge would be infallible. If knowledge were merely relative to points of view, then there would be no grounds for claiming that it can be mistaken. If we refuse ontology (and not merely keep it hidden for strategic, political reasons) then the fallibility of knowledge is unintelligible.

 

The second fear, of determinism, is based on the idea that attributing essences to things or talking of human nature will lead to a radical underestimation of contingency, novelty, variety and indeed the scope for social and political change, hence leading to a kind of knowledge that affirms the status quo rather than being emancipatory. Here it is important not to confuse essentialism with determinism, and given her advocacy of an Aristotelian perspective, it is puzzling that van Staveren should appear to do so. As John O’Neill has argued, from an Aristotelian position, when we denote something as having an essence, we distinguish between its essential properties – the ones that make it that kind of object rather than another, and its accidental properties – which it may or may not have, and which don’t make it a different kind of object (O’Neill, 1994; see also C. Lawson, 1999). The essence of water can be defined as H20; whether it is in the form of rain or a river is a matter of accident rather than essence. Water has certain causal powers, for example the ability to turn into steam at a certain temperature and pressure, but whether these are ever activated depends on contingently related conditions. A particular body of water may exist forever without turning into steam. Its essence therefore does not determine but merely constrains and enables what happens to it. Similarly, possession of a womb may enable conception but does not determine that its possessor ever conceives. Thus, as Lawson argues via a critical realist route (Lawson, 2003, p. 239), talk of human nature need not imply determinism.

 

Nor need it imply exact uniformity. Nature is not uniform but differentiated, and often in complex ways that elude simple descriptions and dichotomies; for example, human biological sex is not simply dimorphic. (Most empirical regularities are only approximate. This is in keeping with the critical realist argument, developed at length by Lawson, that the vast majority of systems are open and hence unlikely to produce exact and enduring regularities.) Deterministic and narrow conceptions of human nature which exclude or pathologise particular groups should obviously be thrown out – but they should be replaced by non-deterministic and inclusive conceptions which are sensitive to physical variety, the deeply social nature of human being and the capacity for cultural variety (Dupré, 2002).

 

Anti-essentialism has been dominant in feminism, and not surprisingly, for gender surely has no essence. Gender does not have a stable, uniform fixed set of characteristics; rather the term refers to common bundles of associations and contrasts and axes of domination that are contestable and shift continually across space and time. However it simply does not follow that because gender has no essence, nothing has any essence. It may be that the concept of essence is not much use in social science because most social phenomena lack the fixity and uniformity associated with the term, though most are not merely ephemeral either. Many social phenomena, like gender and families, are only relatively enduring and varied in form and continually mutating. With its concepts of structures, causal powers and susceptibilities, and its focus on social relations as the primary object of study, critical realism offers a more flexible way of dealing with objects which are only relatively enduring and which at any time exhibit considerable variation. The structures and powers can change, indeed sometimes through autopoieisis, though at any particular time, they cannot do just anything.

 

While anti-essentialism might appear to liberate those whose oppression has been legitimized by being (mis)represented as naturally-grounded, if it also denies that we have any particular properties as human beings, as organic bodies, then it loses all critical purchase on any oppressive exercise of power, particularly through torture, mutilation or abuse (Soper, 1995a, p.138). This is disastrous for emancipatory movements. As Kate Soper argues, in

"denying that there are any instincts, needs, pleasures or sensations which are not simply the effects of culture but impose their own conditions upon its 'constructions', then it is difficult to see what sense we can make of the notion of feminist reclamations of the body or selfhood from the distorting and repressive representations to which they have been culturally subjugated." (Soper, 1995b, 23).

 

As regards universalism and appeals to human nature, there are dangers of identifying local and historically-specific characteristics as universal, and of failing to take seriously the remarkable variety of cultural forms, including gender orders, which shape people deeply. In response to the treatment of local variants as universal or as the norm, and the common tendency to naturalise contingent historical forms of domination, it is tempting to reject any notion of human nature. Human beings are indeed extraordinarily diverse, but we should ask what is it about them which enables them to exhibit such variety? Humans can be profoundly culturally shaped in a vast variety of ways, but not just anything can be culturally shaped. A lump of rock cannot take different cultural forms (it may be externally construed in different culturally mediated ways, and used in various ways, but limestone doesn’t change its nature when we think about it differently, any more than the earth changed shape when we decided it was round rather than flat.) Certain other species are capable of cultural variation too, but that just begs the same question: what is it about them which enables this? For it to be possible for anything to be shaped in a particular way (for example by culture) it must be the kind of thing which is susceptible to such shaping, that is, it must have (or have acquired) the affordances and resistances which allow such shaping. As Andrew Collier points out, far from removing the question of human nature, the phenomenon of cultural variety actually poses it. It presupposes a universal human capacity for cultural variation. Thus, a certain kind of universalism – though not uniformity, with which it is often confused – is presupposed by cultural variety (Collier, 2003). In this way, using a structured ontology, we can understand both sameness and difference: we can see that multiple variants and outcomes can be generated on the basis of common structures (see Lawson, 2003, p. 242). The abstract level does, contra van Staveren, “allow for relations and differences”, for social structures are constituted by internal relations and the whole point of abstraction is to tease out relations and differences that enable and constrain the blizzard of empirical data, and to distinguish which things are merely contingently associated and which necessarily or internally related (Sayer, 2000).

 

Moreover, in line with Soper’s point, we need to identify the capacities of humans – and indeed other species - for flourishing and suffering, and their needs (Lawson, 2003), thus enabling critiques of not just economic theories but economic practices in terms of their effect on people’s well-being. This accords with the Aristotelian position of Martha Nussbaum, who has made important contributions to feminist development theory (Nussbaum, 2000). To be sure there are many different forms of flourishing and different cultures provide different conceptions of what constitutes flourishing, and Nussbaum attempts to accommodate this. But not just anything can be passed off as flourishing. If we were to insist that it was purely culturally relative then we would have no warrant for using terms like ‘oppression’. Again we encounter a relation between general human needs and specific, contingent variants, such as the general psychological need for recognition and the innumerable forms that recognition takes in different cultures. This is why Nussbaum describes her conception of the good as a ‘thick vague’ one, for while it includes many conditions of flourishing, they are expressed in terms vague enough to allow for cultural variation and hence avoid ethnocentrism. This also seems compatible with van Staveren’s largely favourable commentary on Aristotle’s and Adam Smith’s discussions of virtues, which mostly abstract from cultural variations (van Staveren, 1999).

 

We cannot avoid some kind of universalism. Different cultures provide different norms but this presupposes that one of the distinctive features of humans is that they can understand, internalise or contest these, often through exploiting tensions and contradictions within cultural discourses, as in the case of the tension between ideals of equality and gender inequalities. The feminist literature, including van Staveren’s own work on the ethic of care presupposes that all humans are in need of care at various times in their lives, albeit in different ways. People are not just beings who have preferences and make choices, but beings who are vulnerable, and dependent on care. Thus all economies depend on, and distribute the provision and receipt of care. One of the contributions of this literature is to improve our economic theories by enriching our understanding of what it is to be human.

 

 

Emotions

 

Van Staveren endorses Julie Nelson’s claim that critical realism has a built-in bias against emotion, counterposing this to science and reason. This mistakes realism for positivism. Critical realists Margaret Archer and Andrew Collier insistently reject the opposition of reason and emotion, arguing that emotions have a cognitive element, providing an embodied, usually unarticulated commentary on the world and our situation within it, often providing highly perceptive discriminations among situations (Archer, 2000, 2003; Collier, 2003). Hence both authors emphasize and value the intelligence of emotions. As Martha Nussbaum puts it, emotions are evaluative judgements regarding matters affecting or likely to affect well-being (Nussbaum, 2001). There is no reason why critical realists should not be comfortable with the idea of emotional reason. We are angry or happy about things, proud or ashamed of actions. We are more emotionally affected by the loss of a loved one than the loss of a pencil because the former is more important for our well-being: the differences in emotional responses are rational. Emotional reason involves a largely pre-discursive evaluation of things such as the way others treat us and the effect that this is having or is likely to have on us, for example whether they are respecting or humiliating us, befriending or threatening us. Emotions also reflect our deeply social nature (another universalist claim), for as social beings we are psychologically dependent on others for their recognition, love and approval.

 

As a critical realist I would recommend Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments as a remarkable analysis of moral emotions in relation to concrete settings and relationships (Smith, 1759). As Smith emphasizes, the evaluative judgements involved in the various sentiments are fallible, such that, for example, the observer of someone else’s misfortune cannot expect to know exactly what the experience is like for that person. This again is wholly in line with a realist position: for our judgements to be capable of being mistaken, there must be things independent of them about which they can be mistaken. However, although at times our emotional judgements may be ‘illusive’, as Smith put it, for it to be possible for us to live as social actors, our judgements must be fairly adequate for much of the time. Irene van Staveren’s own excellent critique of ‘rational economic man’ is surely a critique of that individual’s lack of a capacity for emotional reason and hence his inability to function as a social actor (van Staveren, 1999). Correcting this is central to a post-autistic economics. For example, as Brennan and Pettit demonstrate, in order to understand the motivations and efforts of workers, paid or unpaid, it is important to appreciate that this is often profoundly affected by whether and how they are esteemed or disesteemed (Brennan and Pettit, 2004). In addition to the invisible hand of market incentives and the visible hand of rules and directives there can be an intangible hand of regulation through esteem.

 

 

Conclusion

 

Anti-realism may be dominant in feminism, though often through a confusion between realism and positivism, but as I have tried to show, feminists can be realists and realists can be feminists, indeed without realism feminism is vulnerable to being dismissed as a form of relativism.  For further arguments on the need of feminism to be realist, I refer readers to the work of Kate Soper (1995a and b), Caroline New (1998, 2003, 2004); and Linda Martín Alcoff (2005).

 

 

References

 

Alcoff, L. Martín (2005) ‘The metaphysics of sex and gender’, Radical Philosophy, forthcoming

Brennan, G and Pettit, P. (2004) The Economy of Esteem, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Collier, A. (2003) In Defence of Objectivity, London: Routledge.

Dupré, J (2002) Human Nature and the Limits to Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press

Feminist Economics (2003) 9 (1) debate on ‘Is critical realism a useful ontology for feminist economics?’ pp. 93-170.

Groff, R. (2004) “Why Social Theorists Should Care About Metaphysics”, Paper presented to Critical

Realism and the Social Sciences conference, Queen’s University, Kingston, Ontario, 24-5th

September.

Lawson, C. (1999) ‘Realism, theory and individualism in the work of Carl Menger’, in S.Fleetwood

(ed.) Critical Realism in Economics, London: Routledge, pp. 43-62.

Lawson, T. (1997) Economics and Reality, London: Routledge.

Lawson, T. (2003) Reorienting Economics, London: Routledge.

New, C. (1998)  ‘Realism, Deconstruction and the Feminist Standpoint’ in Journal for the Theory of

Social Behaviour, 28, 4, 349-372.

New, C. (2003) ‘Feminism, Deconstruction and Difference’. In J. Cruickshank (ed) Critical Realism: The

Difference it Makes. London: Routledge.

New, C. 2004, ‘Sex and gender: a critical realist approach’, New Formations, forthcoming.

Nussbaum, M.C. 2000, Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach, Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

O’Neill, J. (1994) ‘Essentialism and the market’ The Philosophical Forum, Vol. XXVI (2), pp.87-100.

Sayer, A. (2000) Realism and Social Science, London: Sage.

Smith, A. (1759) The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

Soper, K. (1995a) What is Nature?, Oxford: Blackwell.

Soper, K. (1995b) ‘Forget Foucault?’ New Formations, 25, pp.21-7.

Staveren, I. van  (1999) Caring for Economics: An Aristotelian Perspective, Delft: Eburon.

Staveren, I. van  (2004) ‘Feminism and realism: a contested relationship’ post-autistic economics

review, no. 28, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue28/VanStaveren29.htm.

 

___________________________
SUGGESTED CITATION:
Andrew Sayer, “Feminism, critical realism and economics: a response to Van Staveren”, post-autistic economics review, issue no. 29, 6 December 2004, article 5, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue29/Sayer29.htm