The Riddle of Consumption
Richard D. Wolff (University
of Massachusetts, Amherst, USA)
© Copyright 2004 Richard
D. Wolff
Shaun Hargreaves Heap
recently reminded us (PAER no. 26, 2 August 2004)
that The Affluent Society raises an issue as important today as when
Galbraith wrote nearly fifty years ago. Why do consumers want ever more goods
and services when the evidence suggests that more consumption delivers no
greater happiness? Heap praises, discusses, and adds to Galbraith’s
explanations for this riddle of consumption or what might better be called
the fetishism of consumption. However, neither Galbraith nor Heap recognize,
let alone discuss, one solution to the riddle derived from Marx’s theory of
exploitation. Indeed, capitalist exploitation helps to explain not only the fetishization of consumption, but also neoclassical
theory’s parallel need to ascribe disutility to labor
and a compensatory utility to consumption.
Galbraith and Heap are troubled deeply by the
spectacle of endlessly rising consumption spending, by the acquisitive value
system it reflects and reinforces, and by the negative social effects flowing
from both ever-rising consumption and that value system. The fetishization of consumption strikes them as a serious
social problem. It undercuts the happiness of consumers, threatens the
environment, and increasingly dominates public services and especially
education which they believe could and should be sources of different,
preferable value systems. Galbraith and Heap explain ever-rising consumption
as the effect mostly of qualities they believe to be intrinsic to modern
individuals. For example, people derive utility from consumer goods in terms
of their relative – not their absolute – consumption. As others’ consumption
grows, so too must theirs, thereby generating an endless rise of consumption.
Similarly, people are vulnerable to advertising and mass media that generate
ever new desires and tastes. Today’s desires reflect yesterday’s
circumstances of the past; because former generations scrambled for
subsistence, people keep buying long after subsistence is no longer an issue.
The conventional wisdom that more consumer goods and services is always
better than fewer endures, notwithstanding all the contrary evidence, because
belief in conventional wisdoms is a human predilection. Extending Galbraith’s
psychological explanations, Heap stresses modern identity insecurity. Because
their personal identities are now fluid and hence insecure, people turn to
consumption as the means to define and refine individual identities.
Galbraith and Heap do cite one cause for endless
increase in consumption that is not a matter of individual psychology.
Because rising consumption keeps the masses employed, it brings ever more
people out of absolute poverty. This secures “social harmony” by “mitigating”
the social tensions bred by “social inequality.” While both Galbraith and
Heap are vague on this point, it does represent the germ of a social (dare
one say “objective”) rather than personal, psychological (dare one say “subjective”) theory to
explain ever-rising consumption. However, why settle for a germ when a much
more developed and nuanced social theory of rising consumption is available
from classical political economy and especially from Marx?
John Locke argued that post-feudal European society
could work well, despite the loss of social controls operated by absolutist
feudal hierarchies, if each worker disposed of only as much land as that
worker could farm. He, Thomas Jefferson, and others believed that social
inequalities bred social tensions which risked degeneration into civil chaos
or regression back to feudal absolutism. The tensions could be avoided if
production exhibited a rough equality of labor,
means of labor, and hence reward from labor across individuals. However, the actually existing
capitalism that came increasingly to prevail in post-feudal Europe generated
growing inequality (Adam Smith’s accumulation of land and stock). Capitalism
thus risked social catastrophe and self-destruction unless it could somehow
“mitigate” the rising inequality between, speaking broadly, capital and labor. Smith’s idea was that capitalism might mitigate
deepening inequality by raising consumption. Put bluntly, workers falling
ever further behind and below capitalists in terms of wealth, income, power,
and culture, might accept that if they enjoyed an ever-rising level of
personal consumption. For generations of capitalism’s champions, it thus
became axiomatic that a secure capitalism is one that delivers a rising
standard of consumption to its working classes. Crises threaten not because
rising inequality attends capitalist development, but only when that
inequality is not compensated by rising worker consumption.
Marx’s theory of capitalist exploitation developed
Smith’s idea further and in new directions. In the theory of relative surplus value presented in Capital
vol.1, Marx showed how competition among capitalist firms within
each industry typically generated a secular fall in the value per unit of
each industry’s output. That meant, in Marx’s mathematical model, that the
value of labor power would fall since each item in
the worker’s consumption bundle contained less value. Assuming workers labored the same number of hours and thereby produced the
same value added, the fall in the value of their labor
power left a greater mass and rate of surplus value for their capitalist
employers. In short, more of the value added by laborers
accrued as surplus to their employers as less was returned to them as wages;
the exploitation of labor rose. The real wages of
workers remained the same because the reduced value of their wages matched
the reduced value per unit of the consumer goods they purchased. Marx
concluded that capitalism thus displayed a remarkable self-reinforcing
mechanism: each capitalist’s need for more surplus generated a competition
that provided it for all capitalists.
Marx recognized, however, that this happy
circumstance for capitalists required that workers accept a rising rate of
exploitation and its consequences: rising social disparities between workers’
and capitalists’ wealth, income, power, and culture. If, as Marx no doubt
hoped, workers resented exploitation per se and its increase still more, the
old problem of inequality generating social conflict could resurface with a
vengeance. Marx’s argument implies the two parts that a solution to this
capitalist problem would require. First, the value of labor
power should not fall as much as the unit values of consumer commodities
fell, thereby enabling a rise in real wages. So long as the value of labor power falls, the mass and rate of surplus value
rises to the benefit of all capitalists. Exploitation can thus increase while
workers also enjoy a rising standard of consumption. However, this part of
the solution is not, by itself, sufficient. Rising exploitation still entails
the same set of deepening inequalities that worried the classicals.
Thus the need for the second part of the solution: workers must care much
more about their own level of consumption than about exploitation, rising
exploitation, and deepening social inequality.
Modern capitalism, in those areas where it is the
most secure, reflects the successful combination of both parts of this
solution. Exploitation rises to the benefit of capitalists, while real wages
also rise and workers focus on rising consumption as the point and purpose
of their work. They measure the tolerability of their labor
by the adequacy of its compensation in terms of consumption. At a minimum,
workers accept exploitation and its social consequences because they are
compensated by consumption. Better still, for capitalism’s survival, workers
may come to believe that exploitation does not (or no longer) exist, so that
consumption can be viewed as the compensation simply for labor
activity itself.
For successful modern capitalisms, then, real wages
must rise tendentially and workers must be
ceaselessly reinforced to believe that rising consumption is the adequate,
appropriate reward for their productive efforts. In contrast, unsuccessful
capitalisms are those who do not deliver rising consumption or who cannot persuade
their workers that rising consumption is all that should matter in relation
to their work. In this persuasion,
neo-classical economic theory plays a central role. It teaches that work
necessarily entails an intrinsic disutility compared to consumption which is
an intrinsic utility. Work’s intrinsic disutility flows from exertions of
mind and muscle (as opposed to “leisure”). Each worker rationally balances,
at the margin, the disutility of those exertions against the utility of the
consumption enabled by the worker’s income (revenue from those exertions).
Rationality for workers is defined so as to exclude any thought or action in
regard to exploitation and its social effects. Indeed, neoclassical economics
teaches, contra Marx, that exploitation does not (or no longer) exist; there
is no surplus in production. To the extent that neoclassical economics
informs journalists, politicians, school-teachers, ministers and others, it
organizes the persuasion needed to secure capitalism’s rising rates of exploitation
and the social inequalities thereby deepened.
Marx thus offers a different explanation for the
seemingly endless rise in consumption from those discussed by Galbraith and
Heap. They profess to be mystified as to why people demand more consumption
even though it does not make them “happier” and they resort to rather
simplistic psychological explanations for that demand. In contrast, Marx’s
theory of relative surplus value explains why rising real wages are possible,
why they can occur as a consequence of capitalist competition, and why, in
successful capitalisms, they are accompanied by a consciousness that ever
more consumption is better. For Marx, it is a matter less of intrinsic human
psychology than of an attempt to manage the deepening inequalities of
capitalism.
Such management would fail if workers recognized
exploitation and its social effects and refused to accept personal
consumption as adequate compensation for them. It would fail if workers
reacted to the disutility of their labor by demanding
that the quality of their labor activity be changed
by ending exploitation (rather than or in addition to demanding that their
consumption be increased). It would fail if workers stopped believing that
more consumption is better and focused instead on changing the social
conditions of consumption by, among other measures, eradicating exploitation.
This analysis of rising consumption as a means of
managing the social effects of rising exploitation implies a Marxist critique
of both environmentalism and of socialist politics focused on raising
workers’ wages. On the one hand, environmentalism effectively questions
rising consumption by stressing its disutilities. However, in so far as that recognition
remains disconnected from Marx’s larger argument about exploitation and
rising consumption, environmentalism’s impact will be constrained and
undermined. One the one hand, socialists’ focus on raising wages and
consumption standards mobilizes workers around immediate needs. However, in
so far as that focus subordinates or disconnects from Marx’s central
opposition to exploitation within production, socialists risk becoming
inadvertent adjuncts to capitalism’s successful management of rising
exploitation and its social effects.
______________________________
SUGGESTED
CITATION:
Richard D. Wolff, “The Riddle of Consumption”, post-autistic
economics review, issue no. 27, 9 September 2004, article
2, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReviiew/issue27/Wolff27.htm
|