post-autistic economics review
Issue no. 24, 21 March 2005
article 3

 

 

      issue 24 contents                            PAE Review index                               home page

 

 

 

Modernist and Pre-modernist Explanation in Economics


Kevin Quinn   (Bowling Green State University, USA)

© Copyright 2004 Kevin Quinn

 


Science likes to imagine that it has vanquished religious approaches to the world, but it remains vulnerable to religious criticism precisely because it remains religious in important respects. The idea that truth is singular, rather than potentially plural, that it is non-arbitrary,  and that it is meaningful – all of these dogmas amount to a survival, in the heart of science, of an essentially religious, pre-modern, approach to the world.  The silly, post-modern-inspired argument that science, as one more interpretation of the world, stands on equal footing with religious interpretations, can thus (for different reasons than it imagines: the pre-modernism that clings to science is anti-science, not its essence) gain a foothold. To avoid confusion with religion, science needs to shed its vestigial religiosity and achieve its modernist potential. As Shakespeare knew, reality is “a tale told by an idiot, signifying nothing” – divine or otherwise: it is not an allegory for God – pre-modern science gets that right – but neither is it an allegory for Nature, or Reason or Progress, for Fitness or Complexity or anything else.

 

Pre-modern Science: Smith and Coase on Smith

 

Smith’s concept of The Invisible Hand, many have argued, has roots in theology.  And in general it is easy to find passages in Smith that seem to rely on the notion of a divinely-ordained harmony in the world.  In his essay,  “Adam Smith’s View of Man1,” Ronald Coase argues, contra Jacob Viner, that Smith’s views on psychology in The Theory of Moral Sentiments do not, despite appearances, have theological underpinnings.  Smith, says Coase, in showing “that particular characteristics of human beings which were in various ways disagreeable were accompanied by offsetting social benefits2,” did not typically appeal to a divine harmony as an explanation.  I think he makes a persuasive case in this regard. Smith appeals not to God but to Nature as the well-designing author of our harmonious-despite-appearances psychology.  Coase goes on to say that, in this respect, Smith was essentially an evolutionist before his time: “In all these cases nature, as Adam Smith would say, or natural selection, as we would say, has made sure that man possesses those properties which would secure the propagation of the species. (emphasis added).3

 

Examine this astonishing statement. To vindicate Smith’s scientific credentials, Coase assimilates a patent providentialism to modern science! What is the difference that makes a difference between an evolutionist providentialism and a divine one? And yet, of course, to this day evolutionary theory is marred by such providentialism  – a thoroughly anti-scientific excrescence. The idea that evolution promotes the good of the species is more or less gone, thankfully – though it had a long run. But the idea that evolution promotes the good of the organism is alive and kicking.  The fact that Darwin himself, in his theory of sexual selection, rejected this more subtle species of providentialism, has not prevented its remaining intact in biology until fairly recently. But we still have prominent evolutionists trying to explain the human brain, human art and science, human morality, by appeal to the survival value of these innovations – and rejecting more or less out of hand explanations that fail to identify such survival value. 

 

The history of the reception of the theory of sexual selection in biology, recently well recounted by Geoffrey Miller in his book, The Mating Mind4, is a case study in the struggle of the pre-modern and the modern in science, and can serve as a preliminary to a more general discussion of the elements of what I am calling modernist explanation. This will be followed by an account of the struggles of modernism in that most pre-modern of sciences, economics, culminating in a claim that the real scandal that Keynes’ work represented for the discipline was its modernism.

 

Sexual selection, especially the idea of runaway sexual selection developed by H. A. Fisher in 19305, makes clear in a startling way that adaptive traits may hinder the organism’s chances of survival. The peacock’s tail, famously,  reduces the peacock’s chances of survival but increases the chances that its genes will spread by making it more attractive to mates. A providentialist may still take solace in the thought that the female preference for long tails remains unexplained, but here is where, in its runaway version, sexual selection becomes strikingly modern, in my terms: the female preference for long tails, so the theory goes, can be self-justifying. If enough females have a bias toward longer tails in mates, the preference for longer tails will be adaptive, by leading to offspring with longer tails who will be preferred as mates!  Certain conceptions of science, those I am calling pre-modern, find this sort of theory prima facie absurd. It opens the door, patently, to arbitrariness and indeterminacy and unpredictability: why not short tales? The ground starts to slip out from under the explanation: how can a “scientific” explanation make something, in effect, its own cause? And providentialism is obviously shaken to its roots by this sort of thinking, Miller summarizes the reaction to Fisher of the famous biologist Julian Huxley: “He defined evolutionary progress as ‘improvement in efficiency of living’ and ‘increased control over and independence of the environment’. Since sexual ornaments had high costs that undermined survival chances and did not help an animal cope with a hostile environment, Huxley viewed them as anti-progressive, degenerate indulgences6.” Huxley was not unique: sexual selection, which Darwin regarded as equally as important as natural selection, did not enter the mainstream of biological thinking until more than 100 years after Darwin wrote – until the 1980's.

 

The Modern

 

The modernism I want to discuss finds its proper antonym not in  the post-modern but in the pre-modern or traditional. The sense I intend is most adequately delineated in Marshall Berman's All That Is Solid Melts Into Air: The Experience of Modernity7, an enormous and sui generis piece of scholarship. The hallmarks of modernism I want to focus on are, first, the subsumption of ends by means, and, second, closely related, the ubiquity of self-reference.  An example will clarify. How does modern art differ from pre-modern art?  One important way, surely is that for a good deal of the former, art is not the transparent means to an end outside itself, mimesis or representation, but instead becomes its own subject--art about art, art for its own sake, etc. So art, traditionally the means of representing the world, now seeks to represent its own activity--the end has been subsumed by the means in some sense--and self-reference, with its associated paradoxes invariably moves center stage.  An associated idea is that of bootstrap phenomena. Bootstraps, as in "pulling oneself up by one's own" are self-generated or self-caused phenomena. Modern thinking spurns foundations: think of Sartre's notion that man's essence is to have no essence, to be condemned to be free and forced to create his own meaning, willy-nilly. The absence of external foundations, theological or otherwise, makes modernity both exhilarating and terrifying.  It would fill reams and reams of paper to do justice to all the ways in which the theme of means become ends, and the associated themes of self-reference and bootstrapping, are played out in area after area of modern thought and thought about the modern.

 

I don't intend these three elements to capture the richness of Berman's argument, but I believe they are central to modernism in the sense he uses it, although in no way exhaustive of that sense. Summing up his argument, he writes:

To be modern . . . is to experience personal and social life as a maelstrom, to find one's world and oneself in perpetual disintegration and renewal.

 

Examples of "Modernist" Explanation


How and where do we see modernism in this sense in scientific explanation? What follows surveys the ground with a collection of examples, some of which will be further elaborated in later sections.


1. Asset Bubbles: Why does an asset have a high price today? Because it is expected to have an even higher price tomorrow. Alternatively, why does an asset have a low price today? Because it is expected to have an even lower price tomorrow. (See Keynes’ famous Ch. 12 in the  General Theory8, on the stock market as beauty pageant.)

 

2. Increasing Returns: Suppose that there is a positive externality associated with investment, so that the greater the level of aggregate investment, the higher the average level of return on investment. (Investment in knowledge may have this characteristic). Then we can ask, why is the level of investment so high? Because the rate of return on investment is high. But why is the rate of return on investment high? Because the level of investment is high.  Alternatively,--in the same economy, same fundamentals-- why is the level of investment so low? Because the rate of return on investment is low. And why is that? Because the level of investment is low. (See Weill, Phillipe, "Animal Spirits and Increasing Returns”9).

 

3. Conventions: Why do you, an American, drive on the right side of the road? Because you expect others to do the same.  Why do others do so? Because they expect you and others to do so as well. Collectively, then, we drive on the right side of the road because we drive on the right side on the road. Alternatively, why do you, an Englishman, drive on the left side of the road. Because you expect other English people to do the same, etc.

 

4. Money: Why do you give up real goods and services for worthless pieces of paper? Because you expect others to give you (different) real goods and services for the paper in turn tomorrow. Alternatively--same fundamentals--why do you refuse to give up real goods for worthless pieces of paper?  Because you expect others to refuse as well10.

 

5. Co-evolution: Why does animal A have such long, sharp teeth? Because animal B, its prey, has such a hard carapace. Why does animal B have such a hard carapace?  Because animal A, its predator, has such sharp teeth. Alternatively--same fundamentals--why does animal A have such short, dull teeth. Because animal B, its prey, is so soft and mushy. Why is animal B so soft and mushy?  Because animal A, its predator, has such short, dull teeth. (See Sigmund, Games of Life, on co-evolution.11)

 

6.  Runaway Redux: Why is the peacock's tail so long. Because long tails are preferred by females, so the low survival value is offset by the increased chance of mating. But why do females prefer long tails? Because, given a substantial group of females in the population who prefer long tails, a female with a gene for preferring long tails will also carry the gene for long tails. Its offspring will thus do better reproductively.


7. Leijonhufvud’s Keynes: Imagine saving and investment curves as functions of the interest rate. Saving is saving out of full employment income. The intersection determines the Wicksellian natural rate of interest. The investment curve shifts back. The natural rate of interest falls. But bear speculators with inelastic expectations sell bonds to prevent the adjustment. They expect the rate of interest to remain at the old level. Their action leads to a positive gap between full employment saving and investment, a  shifted-in saving function due to falling income, and an equilibrium rate of interest higher than the new natural rate which will now prevail even without speculation. The bears are proved correct. Their expectations that the interest rate would not fall have been confirmed, for the nonce. This is Keynes as interpreted by Axel Leijonhufvud in On Keynesian Economics and the Economics of Keynes12. Why is the rate of interest so high? Because it was expected to be high.

 

8. 19th Century Capitalism: How can the level of investment be so high while the level of consumption is so low?  Means of Production are being produced today to be used to produce means of production tomorrow etc. -- the means have become ends. Alternatively, a low level of investment might make sense despite robust consumption if the level of investment will be low tomorrow -- the means of production needed for the consumption goods industry is high, but the means of production needed to produce means of production are low.

 

So modernist explanations, I shall stipulate, are characterized by:

  1. The ubiquity of self-reference : X because, ultimately, X.
  2. No appeal to fundamentals: God, providence, Reason, Efficiency, Fitness.

c.       The reversal of means/end relationships. Means become ends in themselves.

d.       Bootstrapping phenomena, as in "pulling yourself up by your own" As a consequence, arbitrariness, and multiple equilibria.


Modernism on the Fringe: Marx

 

In economics, the locus classicus of modernism, indeed the source--in the Manifesto-- of the phrase Berman uses as the title of his book, is the work of Karl Marx, definitely far out of the mainstream.  Marx, throughout his writing, returns again and again to the essential difference between a pre-modern economy of small producers where, in his well-known terminology, exchange proceeds according to the transparent schema  C-M-C' (a commodity of one type, C, is exchanged for money, M, which is in turn used to purchase a different commodity C'), on the one hand;  and the modern capitalist economy, whose dynamism springs from its obedience to a diametrically opposed schema: M-C-M', on the other. Here, money purchases commodities (labor and raw materials) which are fashioned into goods to be sold for still more money, so that the process can begin again. Unlike the first, this second process has no natural stopping point, and no foundation or rationale outside of itself, in some pre-existing human needs, the need to satisfy which begins and the satisfaction of which ends the exchange process in the first schema. The mere means in the first schema, money, has become the end in the second.  And what is the money for?  To create more money. Thinking about the second schema, we experience the same dizziness, the same hall-of-mirrors effect that I would argue characterizes the modernist turn in all areas of life and culture. (I think of this modernist experience as the Land 'O Lakes effect, after the butter box of my youth, which pictures an Indian woman holding a box of butter, on which is pictured an Indian woman holding a box of butter, on which is pictured . . .)  Marx's most succinct definition of capital captures this modernist theme beautifully. He calls capital "self-expanding value".  Again we have a self-referring infinity in which means has become end: value creating value creating value . . . . Our pre-modern, traditionalist, religious inclination is to ask "to what end?" and to feel frustrated by our inability to get an answer.

 

Marx argued that to represent the modern capitalist economy as, underneath the trappings of a sophisticated financial system and a highly complex division of labor, nothing but a barter economy operating according to C-M-C', a giant means to satisfy the end of human consumption, was a huge mistake.  He raged against the  "Robinsonades" of the classical economists -- their attempts to explain the workings of a modern capitalist economy by telling stories about Robinson Crusoe solving his economic problem (the economic problem) all alone on his desert island.  The idea that capital, the dynamic process of self-expanding value whose revolutionary consequences Marx documented, could be understood by analogy with the fishing net that Robinson sacrificed some potential fish today to construct, in order transparently to increase his fish consumption tomorrow -- Marx found absurd and laughable.  On the contrary, the capitalism he saw and described was just as capable of producing means of production today to increase the capacity for producing means of production tomorrow, which in turn would make possible further means of production ad infinitum--to produce for production's sake, as it were.  The  economic world he described, in other words, was a modern economy, not the pre-modern and traditional economy of a Robinson Crusoe. To miss this distinction, Marx would have said, is to miss, in effect, everything.

 

Thoroughly Modern Maynard

 

Prior to Keynes, however, the mainstream of the profession did miss this distinction, and, despite Keynes, still in large part does.  What are the "representative agent " models so beloved of modern macroeconomists, real business cyclists and others, if not hi-tech Robinsonades?

 

I believe Keynes' modernism was pervasive. Its most obvious manifestations, however, can seem at first sight fairly isolated in his work, and have been so treated by his interpreters.  The Keynesian who believes Keynes' message to have been well captured in the Hicksian ISLM apparatus has very little use, it would seem, for Keynes' brilliant Chapter 12 in The General Theory, "The State of Long-term Expectation"13.  Here is Keynes' oft-cited discussion of the Stock Market, of Infinitely-lived Asset valuation in general.  The modernism of this chapter is hard to miss. Here we are asked to contemplate the bootstrap character of the valuation of an open-ended asset whose price today depends on dividends it is expected to pay, to be sure, but also on the price it is expected to have tomorrow, which latter price will depend on the price it is expected to have further on in the future, and so on ad infinitum.  Keynes' asks us to take seriously the notion that the asset's price may very well lose any connection with the "solid" fundamentals and become an airy bubble of self-fulfilling expectations.  It is important to see, too, that such an essentially modernist phenomenon Keynes regards not as temporary and bound to disappear just as soon as professionals -- investors knowledgeable about the fundamentals -- appear on the scene, but as comparatively long-lasting and immune to arbitrage:

This battle of wits to anticipate the basis of conventional valuation a few months hence, rather than the prospective yield of an investment over a long term of years, does not even require gulls among the public to feed the maws of the professionals; -- it can be played by professionals among themselves.


Nor is it necessary that anyone should keep his simple faith in the conventional basis of valuation having any genuine long-term validity.  For it is so to speak a game of  Snap, of Old Maid, of Musical Chairs--a pastime in  which he is victor who says Snap neither too soon nor too late, who passes the Old Maid to his neighbor before the game is over, who secures a chair   for himself before the music stops. These games can be played with zest and  enjoyment, though all the players know that it is the Old Maid which is circulating, or that when the music stops some of the players will find themselves unseated.14

In contemporary terms, Keynes is talking in this passage about "rational bubbles".15  They are rational because there is no assumption of stupidity on the part of purchasers of the bubbled asset, stupidity that a canny professional might profit from--and by doing so burst the bubble. The bubbled asset provides a normal return in expectation, with the bubble itself growing at the rate of return, and therefore passes a no-arbitrage or efficient markets test, no matter how wildly divergent from fundamentals its price becomes, and is destined increasingly to become.

 

Only an infinitely-lived agent could undo, via arbitrage, a bubble on an infinitely-lived asset, which fact puts Keynes' reminder that "in the long run we're all dead" in a whole new light!  It is somewhat ironic that the development of rational expectations, a development that in its early stages was used as a battering ram against Keynesian economics, enables us to understand  the bootstraps and bubbles of Chapter 12 Keynes with much greater depth and clarity than we could before.  The determination of the present not by the past but by the unknown future -- via expectations -- can never be grasped, with all its dramatically modernist implications for our economic lives, as long as we reduce expectations about the future, by means of an adaptive expectations scheme, to some determinate function of the past.  Rational expectations -- honestly deployed -- can be a potent generator of modernist outcomes: unfortunately, this is usually noted, if at all, in the footnotes, where one finds the specious arguments for ignoring all but the fundamental solutions covered in the main text.

 

It is important to see that Keynes, despite twinges of pre-modern revulsion which lead him to propose at one point, half-seriously, that we marry the asset to the asset-holder for life, to defeat speculation and thus the melting of all that is solid into air -- ultimately felt that bubbles could not be disposed of so easily: “This is the inevitable result of investment markets organised with a view to so-called liquidity.”16

 

Contemporary thinkers who have carried on and developed Keynes' modernist views of asset bubbles find the profession scarcely more receptive than it was and is to Chapter 12. The pre-modernism of the profession lies very deep: Look, for one example, at the vehemence of the reaction to Robert Shiller's 1981 article on Stock Market volatility, work directly in the tradition of Chapter 12.17  In a symposium on bubbles in the Journal of Economic Perspectives of a few years back, we find one participant arguing quite seriously that the Great Tulip Mania in 17th century Amsterdam--what Sadam Hussein might have called the Mother of All Bubbles, on previous accounts -- can be parsimoniously explained as a response to changes in fundamentals!18

 

But I have argued that modernism is pervasive in Keynes, not a phenomenon confined to a chapter here or there.  Here, I want to suggest that we broaden our minds about the Keynesian message and remember, above all that his work stands in two traditions simultaneously, both the mainstream, and the underground, heretical tradition of underconsumption theorists, numbering among its members thinkers such as Marx, Hobson, Major Douglas and Malthus19 -- some of whom Keynes explicitly acknowledges as progenitors in his appendices to the General Theory.  The common vision of this latter tradition is the one I have identified in Marx, of a modern capitalist economy  subject to stagnation because its ability to produce outruns its ability to consume: the modernist possibility of production for production's sake is here taken very seriously indeed.

 

Moderns and Pre-Moderns: Keynes, Robertson, and Our Grandchildren

 

The modernist impulse in Keynes can be observed in the reaction it provoked in his anti-modernist contemporaries.  A small but symptomatic incident provides an illustration.  Keynes' theory of liquidity preference contained the modernist idea that what determines the interest rate today is speculator's expectations of what it will be tomorrow.  This couldn't be the end of the story, D. H. Robertson20 and others (Leontief, famously) insisted: Where were the fundamentals of the process?  Robertson's reaction was vehemently anti-modernist:

Thus the rate of interest is what it is because it is expected to become other than it is; if it is not expected to become other than it is, there is nothing left to tell us why it is what it is.  The organ which secretes it has been amputated, and yet it somehow still exists--a grin without a cat.21

Robertson is not alone among economists in thinking that to establish the bootstrap, foundation-less character a theory attributes to an economic phenomenon is ipso facto  to refute that theory.  Alice in Wonderland is one thing; reality cannot have this airy character.  If your theory tells you it does, it must need work.  As with under-consumption, I cite this aspect of Keynes as an instance of his attraction to modernist explanations.  I don't mean to condition my argument on an acceptance of the speculative demand for money any more than on the acceptance of, say, Alvin Hansen's Keynesian Stagnationism.  There are contemporary theories of the interest rate which inherit from Keynes the modernist form without the particular content he filled it with.

 

Keynes himself, like many another great modernist, combines his modernist description with a deep anti-modernist revulsion at the prima facie absurdity  of the phenomena he is transcribing  and, in his weaker moments, with what amounts to a pious hope for an overcoming of modernism and a return to a pre-modern golden age where means have been put back in their place as means to independent ends to which they are transparently related, where bubbles have burst and social life, as it were, makes sense again. (Berman, by the way finds some of these same tendencies in the arch-modernist Marx, who seems sometimes to hold up a vision of socialism as a rest from the ceaseless flux, an overcoming, indeed, of history, a putting-paid to the ceaseless, permanent revolution of modern life.)

 

This modernist/anti-modernist dialectic in Keynes is most apparent in his 1930 essay, "Economic Possibilities for our Grandchildren"22, where he contrasts the "purposiveness" of contemporary economic life with its potential overcoming in the lives of our grandchildren.  The former idea represents still another ringing in Keynes' work of the by now familiar modernist changes.  The purposive man, he says:

 

is always trying to secure a spurious and delusive immortality for his acts by pushing his interest in them forward in time.   He does not love his cat, but his cat's kittens; nor, in truth, the kittens but only the kittens' kittens; and so on forward forever to the end of cat-dom.  To him jam is not jam unless it is a case of jam tomorrow and never jam today.23

 

But after describing and dissecting this modernist purposiveness--interestingly named since it seems almost paradigmatically anti-purposive to pre-modern eyes--Keynes sounds an almost religious anti-modernism.  The purposive era will one day end ("when science and the power of compound interest " have solved the economic problem!).  And in this future made possible precisely by virtue of the abundance obtained through centuries of purposiveness:

 

We shall once more value ends above means and prefer the good to the useful.  We shall honor those who teach us to pluck the day virtuously and well, the delightful people who are capable of taking direct enjoyment in things, the lilies of the field, who toil not, neither do they spin.24

 

But Keynes, unlike the great majority of the economics profession in his day and our own, did not allow his anti-modern hopes and values -- delusive or not -- to interfere with his ability to limn the modernist reality in which we live and breathe. The modernist present is highlighted and set off by the stark contrast with the imagined anti-modernist future.

 

Keynes' modernism is, I believe, the most deeply interesting and at the same time has proven so far the least assimilable dimension of his legacy to the economics profession.

 

L’Envoi

 

Taking the contra-positive formulation of Nietzsche’s famous declaration, if everything is not permitted, then God is not dead.  A determinist science, science that recoils from arbitrariness and meaninglessness, that doesn’t permit, in principle, everything, that only counts as explanations the pre-modernist subset – keeps God alive, and its adherents children.



Notes


1. Coase, Ronald, 1994. Essays on Economics and Economists. University of Chicago Press, Chicago: 95-118.

2. Ibid: 107.

3. Ibid: 109.

4. Miller, Geoffrey, 2000.  The Mating Mind. Doubleday, New York.

5. Sigmund, Karl, 1993. Games of Life. Oxford University Press, New York: 128-31.

6. Miller, op. cit: 58.

7. Berman, Marshall,1982, All That Is Solid Melts Into Air, Penguin Books, New York.

8. Keynes, J. M., 1965, The General Theory, Harbinger, New York.

9. Weill, Philipe, 1989."Animal Spirits and Increasing Returns.” American Economic Review: September.

10. See Wallace, Neil, 1980. "Overlapping Generations Models of Fiat Money" in Models of Monetary Economies. Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis.

11. Sigmund, op. cit.: 148, et seq. , on co-evolution.

12. Leijonhufvud, Axel, 1968. On Keynesian Economics and The Economics of Keynes. Oxford University Press, London.

13. Keynes, J. M., 1965, The General Theory, Harbinger, New York: 147-164.

14. Keynes,1965, op.cit.,p.155.

15. See Blanchard, Olivier and Stanley Fischer (1989), Lectures on Macroeconomics, MIT Press, Cambridge, Chapter 5, for a good discussion of this literature. Chapter 5 is titled "Multiple Equilibria, Bubbles and Stability", and it sits uncomfortably in the text, an apparent swerving away from the main track (which of course it is). The last sentence of the chapter states ". . . though we find the phenomena analyzed in this chapter both interesting and disturbing, we are willing to proceed on the working assumption that the conditions need to generate stable multiplicities of equilibria are not met in practice". So it's goodbye to bubble solutions from then on. I wonder how many syllabi in courses that use the text leave this chapter out?

16. Ibid, emphasis added.

17. Shiller, Robert,(1989), Market Volatility, MIT press, Cambridge, contains the original article along with Shiller's responses to the veritable cottage industry of critics which grew in its wake. The article is "Do Stock Prices Move too Much to be Justified by Subsequent Changes in Dividends", American Economic Review 71 (1981): 421-35, and appears as Chapter 5 of Market Volatility.

18. Garber, Peter, (1990), "Famous First Bubbles", Journal of Economic Perspectives 4: 35-54.

19. See Bleaney, Michael, Underconsumption Theories, (1976), International Publishers, New York, for an excellent overview of this tradition.

20. Robertson, D. H.,(1940), "Mr. Keynes and the Rate of Interest" in Essays in Monetary Theory, Staples Press, London:1-38.

21. Ibid.: 25.

22. In Keynes, (1963), Essays in Persuasion, Norton, New York: 358-373.

23. Ibid: 370.

24. Ibid: 372.

______________________________
SUGGESTED CITATION:
Kevin Quinn,
“Modernist and Pre-modernist Explanation in Economics”, post-autistic economics review, issue no. 24, 15 March 2004, article 3, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue24/Quinn24.htm