Seven Theses for a Theory
of Realist Economics*
Jacques Sapir (L'École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales,
Paris)
© Copyright 2003, Jacque Sapir
In Part I, which appeared in the last issue, Jacques
Sapir argued that post-autistic or realist
economics needs to develop a coherent research program. To this end he proposed to offer seven
theoretical theses and introduced the first four.
Thesis
1: The central issue in economics is the co-ordination of decisions and
interactions generated by decentralised, heterogeneous and interdependent
agents whose decision-making abilities are constrained by limited cognitive
capacities.
Thesis
2: If money is a necessity in an uncertain world, money also introduces a
specific form of uncertainty, casting doubts on the market’s ability to
efficiently process information.
Thesis
3: Time and money are at the very heart of the interchange between the
individual and collective levels.
Thesis
4: Any attempt to negate the theoretical status of time and money leads to
non-scientific assumptions and transforms the economist himself into a
producer of ideology.
Part II: Theses Five to Seven
Thesis 5: To regard money as the one central institution in a market
economy fails to break free from the neo-classical framework. Emphasizing
only money could be as theoretically misleading as ignoring money.
It is clear that understanding
money’s relevance is a cornerstone of economic theory. Yet this position can evolve into a
mistaken one no less dangerous than the neo-classical denial of money’s
relevance: monetary essentialism. It is the path taken by two French authors
with whom otherwise I generally agree, Michel Aglietta
and André Orléan, the latter a well-known and
long-standing PAE contributor. Because they claim to have developed a
workable alternative to the money denial strategy favoured by neo-classical
and some Marxist authors alike34, an alternative giving monetary
policy and Central Bank independence a strong legitimacy, monetary
essentialism is worth serious investigation. As a matter of fact, if one
could demonstrate that money is as pivotal as monetary essentialism pretends
it is, then one would have a pretty good argument for asserting the
superiority of monetary authorities over political ones.
Monetary essentialism moves beyond acknowledging money relevance against the
neo-classical cum monetarist tradition to the point of proclaiming money the
central, pivotal, market economy institution35. It acknowledges
the fact there is a deeply entrenched violence in monetary relations which
cannot be reduced to just an allocative process.
Monetary essentialism is innovative in its aim of linking economics to
anthropology and it is grounded on what Aglietta
and Orlean call the Fundamental Girardian
Theorem from the French catholic philosopher and anthropologist René Girard36.
Years ago Girard developed an anthropological theory of violence that he
opposes to one emphasizing the social roots of conflicts. His theory is
grounded on the genesis of violence erupting from an undifferentiated mob
driven by a demand for wealth. This word resonates in the economist's ears.
However in Girard's works wealth is an all-encompassing notion running from
material goods and money to social status and parental love. Because it is
such a global, all encompassing notion, it makes it possible to conceive of a
universe of one-dimensional choices where "wealth" is the measure
of everything. This conception resembles the neoclassical concept of price
which is supposed to carry all needed information. In a Girardian
world an economist would be, to paraphrase Oscar Wild, a cynic who knows the
wealth of everything and the value of nothing. In this universe of
one-dimensional choices, individual preference transitivity could then be
logically demonstrated and the neoclassical theory of preference and
rationality given a new rationale. One could then forget that in the real world,
and specifically when money is at stake, it has been demonstrated that
violations of transitivity are systematic37.
It is, however, perfectly clear that the Girardian
genesis of violence is no less unrealistic and anti-social than the Robinson
Crusoe metaphor that Austrian marginalists were so
fond of. All the perfumes of Girardian wealth could
not sweeten the neo-classical price. Aglietta and Orléan run into a
serious contradiction. Admirably they profess their willingness to break with
the neo-classical logic. However as they pretend to reject the view of a
fully determined world - a position I completely share with them - they fall
into another fallacy, the one of pretending that there are no so central
rules but money. To do so they have to stick with violence as understood by
René Girard38. Then they have to pretend that there is no stable
social relation between agents, that they are un-socialised social actors39.
This is one dimension of the neoclassical fallacy. The so-called Fundamental Girardian Theorem is supposed to say that unanimity could
be the result of a spontaneous convergence, hence the undifferentiated demand
for wealth could give birth to a global social agreement. However Orléan remarks with some ingenuity that if we introduce
one differentiation level in the primitive wealth-driven population then
unanimity is no longer a spontaneous result40. Change here
unanimity for equilibrium and you would have an exact restatement of the
Grossman-Stiglitz paradox41. The Girardian Theorem’s sensitiveness to heterogeneity is
another proof that it is a next of a kin to the neo-classical equilibrium and
Girardian wealth to Walrasian
price. Anyone here cruel enough into introduce in the picture the endowment
effect and the framing effect would lead the Girardian
Theorem to its self-destruction and monetary essentialism to its
methodological collapse.
What is problematical with monetary essentialism is not its emphasis on
violence or its attempt to link economics to anthropology. The problem lies with
the anti-social anthropology that it mobilises, a theory leading not to a
definitive break with neo-classical orthodoxy but to the reverse, a return
toward typical neoclassical simplifications and methodological unrealism.
Thesis 6: The idea that there is one pivotal institution for a market
economy is devoid of meaning. Institutions cannot be assessed in
isolation. What matter are
institutional systems or precisely defined hierarchical clusters of
institutions.
If money cannot be seen as the central institution of a market economy, then
maybe property rights could be seen as an alternative42. After
all, without property rights it is difficult to understand market
transactions. However when one discusses property rights it is frequently
private property which is at stake. But, as explained years ago by Richard
Nelson, private property does not work as an operational concept enabling us
to delineate differences between forms of social organisation43.
To oppose private to collective ownership is to run quickly into an
interesting, if frequently forgotten, paradox.
If property rights are to be defined inside a society, then we have more than
one economic agent to think about. Hence, what agent (a) is doing could
affect in an unintentional way the wealth and position of agent (b). The
latter could sue the former who then would think twice before doing anything
if the penalty were significant by comparison to the expected result form his
own action. This is nothing more than a restatement of the Shackle Paradox,
explaining that decentralised decision-making gives birth to uncertainty and
that uncertainty could prevent decentralised agents from making decisions44.
To prevent unintentional effects from paralysing the whole social life, every
society has developed a different set of rules for actually constraining our
individual freedom to use and abuse our properties. Rules, without which no
individual action is possible in a society, are nothing less than collective
property rights. Hence, individual property rights can't exist without
collective ones. And if to avoid this problem we attempt to define individual
property rights from the Robinson Crusoe metaphor, then we define something
that does not exist. Before the landing of Friday, Robinson, alone on his
island, owns everything that is nothing. Property rights here have no
meaning.
Private and collective property rights can't be opposed and are actually
closely integrated. But, if we have to think about collective ownership to
understand private ownership then it is mandatory to think about the way
human collectivities are organised. Political
issues (how legitimacy and legality interact) matter then as much as property
rights. They cannot be substituted for money as the pivotal market economy
institution, and I hope that this discussion had made a case against the
whole idea of defining any "pivotal" institution.
Let us now return to the problem of money.
We have to reckon with the fact that barter trade can exist simultaneously
with money, meaning that there is more to be considered than just the fact
that money is a more effective and rational transaction medium than barter45.
The development of barter trade in Russia from 1993 to 1998, a period when
inflation was actually decelerating (barter was at its highest point early
1998 when inflation was down to 12% a year), raises an important theoretical
issue. The use of money receded not because the value of money was
disappearing as happens during a hyperinflation crisis (remember Weimar and
the wheelbarrows full of banknotes) but because institutions, without which
money cannot be used, were missing46. The development of barter
trade in Russia was the result of a lack of financial institutions, the
result of the liberal monetary policy implemented from October 1993 onwards47.
It was also the result of a lack of trust48 resulting from the
weakening of State institutions through the particular privatisation process
then implemented by Anatolyi Chubays
and his US crony advisers49. Money, as an institution, needs both
technical institutions (mostly in the finance sector) and political ones to
support it and make it effective. In turn, after the August 1998 crash,
barter receded not because of any hard monetary policy (actually inflation
rose) but because Primakov's government worked hard
to rebuild state legitimacy and institutions50.
Money can be relevant when two specific freedoms or rights can be found in
any transaction: the freedom to engage in a transaction with whom one wants
and the freedom to engage when one wants. Both these freedoms do not exist
for every possible transaction. Sometimes technical constraints drastically
reduce the first one, so that vertical integration, that is the substitution
of a hierarchy for a market, is then the logical evolution. And social
constraints can reduce both the first and the second freedoms. In any case, these freedoms or rights imply
a whole set of institutions which, in turn, defines the place and form money
can take at a given time in a given market economy.
The central issue is then not the functionality of a single institution but
how institutions in a given set can be mutually supportive. In the end it is
the coherence level achieved by the institutional system that is the
analytical key of statistical stabilities and medium-term trends. When money
is at stake, it is the coherence (or the lack of) between managing
institutions (central bank, financial markets, banking system, international
financial institutions) and related ones (public regulations,
labour-management relations, balance of property rights between individual
and collective ownership, institutional forms of the social protection
system, regulation of human, material and financial trans-border flows) which
really matters. The coherence issue, be it static or dynamic, is then the
central one for realist economics.
Thesis 7: The embededness of any institutional
system in a given territory, itself a social and historical construction, is
an omission of mainstream economics that is hidden behind the denial of time
and money relevance.
Time and money have led us to
institutions. Not just the usual discussion about institution functionality
but to the understanding that an institution cannot be considered in isolation.
Institutional systems, coherent and hierarchal sets of institutions, are the
main issue. Rejecting the functionalist fallacy about institutions means also
rejecting any functionalist understanding of the birth of institutions51.
The Hayekian view of spontaneous selection raises many methodological and
theoretical problems. Among them the two most vexing are:
(a)
the
Hayekian selection process introduces a methodological holism dimension into
an otherwise individualist theory (institutions are selected through groups)
and
(b)
that
without assuming temporal monotony of individual preferences it is impossible
to prove that selection has not been accidental unless one assumes a
stationary universe.
Up to now the only realist theory of institution generation has been François
Guizot's. Social conflicts of opposing human groups
have been the historical process of institutional development and selection52.
The dynamic of these conflicts develops in the space of sovereignty, which is
then shaped by the development of conflicts. Such a process makes the
distinction between rules and the principles on which rules are founded a
pervasive necessity.
Social density implies the necessity of rules, as individual agents are
unable to forecast all possible unintentional effects of their own actions.
This makes then unable to write complete and perfect contracts. Contract
incompleteness and imperfection make rules a necessity. Institutions generate
rules but individual institutions are incomplete as shown above. To make
institutional systems work in a coherent way, rules of a greater magnitude
are needed. They are laws as produced by political institutions. But the
human agent’s inability to write complete and perfect contracts applies here
too. It is then to be expected that laws are to be contested even if the
process under which they have been produced has respected its own rules.
Hence, the rule of Law is not enough or we have to prove that the concerned
human community is perfectly homogeneous and composed only of people driven
by the best set of sentiments possible53. The emphasis put on the
rule of Law, as in the British and American mainstream tradition, reveals a
deep negation of the heterogeneity principle54.
The legality of the process does not confer to a law the legitimacy it needs.
Legitimacy proceeds from principles, which characterises a political
community which, historically, is territorially defined. In turn one can see
how the neo-classical view of a perfect information world is congruent to an
understanding of institutions reduced to their functionality and to the
negation of the legitimacy principle for the sake of making the rule of Law
the one and only one benchmark55.
If we agree to the fact that economics is not a natural science, and to the
contrary that economic processes are embedded in social and historical
construction, then the institution building process is as much political as
it is economic. It cannot be understood separately from links between a given
territory and a political community. Even in the globalisation age,
Nation-State matters. It matters when it exists as well as when, weakened by
decades of neoliberal policies, it is no more able
to play its part. The difference between the way Malaysia rode the financial
storm in 1998 when Indonesia sank is not just a difference between a wise and
an unwise economic policy. The Malaysian state was still functional whereas
the Indonesian one had been dramatically weakened. Malaysian economic and
political elites were then in a position to resist the IMF
policy and implement effective decisions (like the currency control) when
Indonesian elites were so fragmented and deprived of legitimacy that they had
to abide by IMF prescriptions with their usually
catastrophic results56.
If institutional systems cannot be understood in a dynamic way without
including in the picture the way space has been shaped by centuries of social
and political processes and conflicts, economics has no meaning but the one
of political economy. This political economy needs to seriously address the
Nation-State issue as well as the fact that every Nation-State is not fully
homogeneous and that institutional differentiation can be found inside their
own perimeter. Institutional differentiation inside a given Nation-State can
explain why regional competitiveness is frequently different and why some
regions develop faster than others do at a given time. In turn this can be
understood only on the basis of acknowledging the social dimension of any
institution, including given sets of markets. The development of an effective
market economy (“effective” and not “efficient” because out of the
neo-classical theoretical frame this word is devoid of meaning) always is the
result of a given social process. Markets are socially constructed objects57.
The development of regional sciences is then a logical and necessary addition
to a comprehensive research program for realist economics58.
Notes
34. M. Aglietta et A. Orléan,
La Violence de la monnaie,
PUF, Paris, 1982; Idem, La Monnaie entre
violence et confiance, Odile
Jacob, Paris, 2002. Both authors explicitely state
their theory is not just a refutation of neo-classical assumptions but also
of the Marxian Theory of Value.
35. M. Aglietta et A. Orléan,
La Monnaie entre violence et confiance,
op.cit., p. 81.
36. A. Orléan, "Monnaie
et spéculation mimétique"
in P. Dumouchel (ed.), Violence et vérité autour
de René Girard, Paris, Grasset, 1978, pp.
147-158.
37. L. Ausubel, "The Failure of Competition in
the Credit-Card Market", in American
Economic Review, vol. 81, n°1/1991, pp. 50-81
38. M. Aglietta, "L'institution
de base des sociétés marchandes"
in Alternatives Économiques,
n°57, 2003, p. 32.
39. A. Orléan, "Monnaie
et spéculation mimétique",
op.cit., p. 148.
40. A. Orléan, "Monnaie
et spéculation mimétique",
p.151 and 152.
41. S.J. Grossman et J.E.
Stiglitz "On the Impossibility of Informationally Efficient Markets" op.cit..
42. O. Hart et J. Moore, "Property Rights and the Theory of the
Firm", in Journal of Political
Economy, vol. 98, n°6, 1990; E.G. Furobtn et S.
Pejovich, "Property Rights and Economic
Theory: a Survey of Recent litterature", in Journal of Economic Litterature,
vol. 10, 1972, n°4.
43. R.R. Nelson, "Assessing Private Enterprise: An Exegesis of Tangled
Doctrine", in Bell Journal of
Economics, Vol. 12, n°1/1981, printemps, pp.
93-111.
44. G.L.S. Shackle, Decision, Order and Time in Human Affairs, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 1969.
45. This opinion has been developed in A. Alchian,
"Why Money?", in Journal of
Money, Credit and Banking, vol. IX, n°1/1977, pp. 133-140. For the
opposite view and a discussion of the simultaneous presence of both money and
barter, J. Sapir, "Le troc
et le paradoxe de la monnaie"
in Journal des Anthropologues,
n°90-91, décember 2002, pp. 283-304.
46. D. Woodruff, Money Unmade: Barter
and the fate of Russian Capitalism, Cornell University Press, Cornell,
1999.
47. J. Sapir, "A l'épreuve
des faits...Bilan des politiques macroéconomiques mises en oeuvre en Russie",
in Revue d'études
comparatives est-ouest, vol.30, n°2-3/1999, pp
153-213.
48. D. Marin, "Trust Vs. Illusion: what is driving demonetization in
Russia?", Discussion paper Series,
n°2570, CEPR, Londres, september 2000.
49. J. Sapir, "La crise
financière russe comme révélateur des carences de la transition libérale"
in Diogène,
n°194, April-June 2001, pp. 119-132.
50. J. Sapir, “Russian crash of August 1998:
Diagnosis and prescriptions”, Post-Soviet
Affairs (ex-Soviet Economy),
Vol. 15, n° 1/2000, pp. 1-36.
51. On the functionalist fallacy, see Stiglitz's
Nobel Lecture, J.E. Stiglitz,
"Information and the Change in the Paradigm in Economics", in American Economic Review, vol. 92,
n°3, juin 2002, pp. 460-501.
52. F. Guizot, Histoire
de la civilisation en France depuis la chute de l'Empire Romain, Didier,
Paris, 1869. 7th lesson, 1828.
53. This argument has been well demonstrated by Carl Schmitt. Although one
may reject his conclusion and be disgusted by his political positions between
1920 and 1945, he certainly is a founding father for a realist understanding
of paradoxes of a democratic society. See C. Schmitt, Legalität und Legitimität, Duncker & Humblot, Berlin 1932 (there is one French translation of
this book as Légalité et Légitimité
but, to the best of my knowledge, none in English); Idem, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy,
MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1985 (1926).
54. See C. Mouffe, "Carl Schmitt and the
Paradox of Liberal Democracy" in C. Mouffe
(ed.), The Challenge of Carl Schmitt,
Verso, London & New York, 1999, pp. 38-53.
55. J. Sapir, Les
économistes contre la démocratie, Albin Michel,
Paris, 2002.
56. For a good discussion about the Asian crisis and different responses put
by different governments, R. Wade, "The Coming Fight Over Capital
Controls" in Foreign Policy,
vol. 113, hiver 1998-1999, pp. 41-54; R. S. Rajan, "Sands in Wheels of International Finance:
Revisiting the Debate in Light of the East Asian Mayem",
Institute of Policy Studies working
paper, Singapour, Avril
1999 and B.J. Cohen, "Contrôle des capitaux :
pourquoi les gouvernements hésitent-ils ?", in Revue économique, vol. 52, n°2/mars
2001, pp. 207-232.
57. A. Bagnasco & C. Trigilia,
La construzione
sociale del mercato. Studi sullo sviluppo
di picola imprese in Italia, Il Mulino,
Bologna, 1988.
58. G. Benko & M. Dunford,
(eds.), Industrial Change and Regional
Development, Pinter/Belhaven Press, London, 1991. G. Benko
& U. Strohmayer (eds.), Space and Social Theory, Blackwell, Oxford, 1997. G. Benko, La Science Régionale, PUF, Paris,
1998.
______________________________
SUGGESTED
CITATION:
Jacques Sapir, “Seven Theses for a Realist Economics; Part II: Theses Five to
Seven”, post-autistic
economics review, issue no. 22,
24 November 2003, article 3, http://www.btinternet.com/~pae_news/review/issue22.htm
|