Capabilities: From Spinoza to Sen and Beyond*
Part II: A Spinoza-Sen Economics Research Program
Jorge
Buzaglo
(formerly
University of Gothenburg, presently in search of funding and affiliation)
© Copyright 2003 Jorge Buzaglo
“Part I: Spinoza’s Theory of
Capabilities” appeared in the last issue
The
Ethics and present-day science
The psychophysical identity theory in Spinoza’s The Ethics is particularly well adapted for the analysis of the
body/mind problem in the framework of present day natural sciences. In
particular, evolutionary theory finds its natural foundation in the notion of
immanent causation inherent to Substance (God or Nature) ─ that which
has itself as its own cause and is not produced by anything external.
Particular entities are modifications or modes
of the Substance, produced by one another in an infinite chain of causation.
According to Henry Atlan (1998, p. 215), “[w]ith such a notion of immanent causality, Evolution can be
seen as the unfolding of a dynamic system, or a process of complexification and self-organization of matter,
produced as the necessary outcome of the laws of physics and chemistry. In
this process, new species come into existence one after the other as effects
of mutations and stabilizing conditions working as their efficient causes,
whereas their particular organizations are particular instances of the whole
process.” The omniform
complexity of the texture of matter/extension corresponds to the omniform complexity of the thought dimension of the
Substance. To the chain of causes in the material domain corresponds an
equivalent chain of causes under the attribute of thought.1 It is
important to remark the absence in this conception of interaction between
matter and thought; both have their own, equivalent causal structures, as
they are two (different) faces of the (same) coin. In his Ethics Spinoza writes:
[A] mental
decision and a bodily appetite, or determined state, are simultaneous, or
rather are one and the same thing, which we call decision, when it is
regarded under and explained through the attribute of thought, and a conditioned
state, when it is regarded under the attribute of extension, and deduced from
the laws of motion and rest (3.2, Note).
Or, as emphatically stated
in 3.2: Body cannot determine mind to
think, neither can mind determine body to motion or rest or any state
different from these, if such there be.
However, the idea that the decisions of the mind determine the actions of the
body is deeply rooted in our intuitive (unreflective) view of our actions.
This is due, thinks Spinoza, to the fact that, in general, we are aware of
our desires and intentions, but unaware of the causes that motivate these
desires and intentions (2.35, Note; 3.2, Note).2 The belief is so
entrenched that it is merely at the bidding of the mind that the body
performs its actions, says Spinoza (3.2, Note), that only experimental proof
may eventually induce us to change our minds.
Now, it seems that neuroscience can today supply the conditions for an
experimental proof of immanent causation, and convincingly reject the hypothesis
of mental causation of bodily action. As reported by Atlan
(1998), Libet (1985) consistently found that a
conscious decision to act corresponds to an electrical brain event which
occurs 200 to 300 milliseconds after
the beginning of action. This experimentally reproducible fact, consistent
with the above “monist” model, falsifies the conventional idea of
mind-determined bodily action. The action of the body is triggered by some
neuronal unconscious stimuli. That is, a physical impulse determines a bodily
movement. Accompanying that action there is a conscious observation with an
understanding of the action. The conscious observation accompanies the
action, but it is not its cause. The psychic decision and the neural impulse
are identically equivalent, each within their own domain of
existence/description.3 This fact has of course important
consequences for our understanding of homo
oeconomicus, and for what can be accepted as
meaningful explanation in economic theory.
Economic theory after The Ethics
The effects of the above
insights on conventional economic theorising are, I think, devastating. The
utility maximizing individuals of conventional theory are isolated minds
commanding bodily actions. Homo oeconomicus is a mind with a particular preference
system and a perceived resource constraint commanding a body to perform
specific actions (purchases and sales) in a marketplace. This mind is
conscious of its own actions, and ignorant of the causes by which it is
conditioned. This idea of “rational choice” simply reflects ignorance of any
cause for the agent’s actions.
That is, the homo oeconomicus
model of conventional microeconomics does not specify how the preferences of
the mind have been themselves determined, and even less how the mind determines
the body to perform its “optimal” decisions in the market. Microeconomics is
totally silent on how and where this interaction could take place. The model
of man propounded by microeconomics simply eludes the problem of interaction.
The man of microeconomics should more accurately be named homunculus oeconomicus. In cognitive science, the homunculus is an implausible little
man inhabiting the brain and embodying an uncaused will making choices and
commanding the body to execute them.4
The canonical model of body/mind dualism is still that of Descartes in Traité des Passions de l’Ame
(1.50). In Descartes, the will, located in the pineal gland, receives
signals and sends impulses ─ by means of the bodily humours (esprits animaux) ─ to other parts of the body.5
But, as Spinoza argues (Part 5, Preface) it is not possible to have
non-physical entities acting on material objects (deus ex machina) as an acceptable form of
rational explanation. Should an interactive mechanism ever get specified, it
would absorb the non-physical antecedent into the physical consequent.6
In The Ethics, individual entities are, as described in the previous
section, causally interconnected in an unlimited web of modifications (modes) of the uncaused Substance (causa sui). The
ideas of the mind are causally connected to other ideas, as bodies in space
are causally interrelated. Yet this does not exclude autonomy and
responsibility. On the contrary, individual entities endeavor
to exist according to their own individual nature (3.6):
Everything, in so far as it is in itself, endeavors to persist in its own being.
For Spinoza (3.7), the
actual essence of a thing is nothing else but this endeavor
to persist in its own being (conatus).
The mind endeavors to persist in its being, and is
conscious of it (3.9).An implication
of conatus, as formulated in the Theologico-Political
Treatise, is that
[…]
no man’s mind can possibly lie wholly
at the disposition of another, for no one can willingly transfer his natural
right of free reason and judgment, or be compelled to do so… All these questions fall within a man’s
natural right, which he cannot abdicate even with consent. (Spinoza 1951,
p. 257, quoted from Ellerman 1992, pp.144-5)
______________________________
SUGGESTED CITATION:
Jorge Buzaglo, “Capabilities: From Spinoza to Sen; and
Beyond; Part II: A Spinoza-Sen Economics Research
Program”, post-autistic economics review,
issue no. 21, 13 September 2003,
article 2, http://www.paecon.net/PAEReview/issue21/Buzaglo21.htm
|